Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie - Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature ...
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie © Logos, I. Antiquity Alfred Dunshirn The word logos generally refers to the (spoken) word, though it should be borne in mind that this does not mean a single word but the combination of several words. An ancient encyclopaedia entry – the 100th of the pseudo-Platonic Definitions – defines logos as “a voice in signs that can name every single thing that exists” (Horoi). The verb belonging to logos is legein, it designates speaking as well as picking up or collecting. Thus, logos can be understood as selecting and meaningfully compiling. This in turn shows that logos as an assembly or “interweaving” (Plato) of words can refer to a narrative, a sentence, a speech or an argument as well as to a proportion or a measure. In Early Greek thought, Heraclitus uses logos to refer to an entity that holds together the conflicting forces of the cosmos. In Platonic-Aristotelian philosophy, as with the Sophists, one can observe the discussion of various kinds of logoi to which truth and falsity are attributed. In the Stoa, the logos becomes the (materially conceived) divine, which determines everything in the world completely rationally. In ancient Christian literature, which was strongly influenced by Neoplatonism, logos finally appears in the “event of Jesus Christ” (Bultmann) as “the WORD”, as the divine demand that reveals itself to mankind. The outstanding significance of the various conceptions of logos in European intellectual history is apparent not least in the critique of logocentrism, as formulated above all in the 20th century. Citation and license notice Dunshirn, Alfred (2021): Logos, I. Antiquity. In: Kirchhoff, Thomas (ed.): Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature / Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie. ISSN 2629-8821. doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 This work is published under the Creative Commons License 4.0 (CC BY-ND 4.0) denoted (exciting, entertaining, deceptive or comfort- 1. Linguistic ing) narratives, from the fifth century B.C. onwards a The Greek word logos is a derivative of the verb legein, broadening of the range of meanings in the texts of which initially meant “harvest”, “to unite” and “to collect” early Greek thinkers can be detected (Johnstone 2014: as well as “to tell”, “to talk” and “to speak”, later “to 12–17). The term logos then also denotes the argument count” (Frisk 2006: 94–96; Beekes 2010: 841 f.). Accord- independent of the concrete speaker, an explanation, ingly, the noun logos, plural logoi, designates various the object of investigation, a justification, as well as types of “collections”, be it links of words as “narratives”, that in which the reasoning and linguistic faculty is “sentences”, “statements”, “arguments” and (vocally located, the mind and reason; logos can finally be used communicated) “speeches” or also connections of to refer to a relation in the sense of a mathematical ratio, numbers in “calculations”, “counts” or “measures”. as indicated by the expression “ana-logous”; in Christian We first encounter the word logos in literature in the literature logos stands for the “WORD of God” (Liddell/ Homeric epics (e.g. Iliad XV, 393). Researchers dispute Scott 1996: 1057–1059; Bauer 1958: 942–947). Related whether in these early texts the basic meaning of legein to Greek legein and logos are Latin legere and German is the (numerical) “counting” or the “summarising” and lesen as well as numerous derivatives from Latin in “grouping”, from which the later common meaning modern languages, such as English “collect”. “telling” resulted. (On the primacy of “telling” over The term logos does not indicate a single word – the “counting” see Gianvittorio 2010: 140–146, on legein in terms onoma, “name”, “noun”, and rhema “utterance”, the context of forming quantities see Castoriadis 1990: “verb” serve to designate such a word – but at least a 372–454). While logoi in early Greek poetry mainly sentence, i.e. the combination of an onoma (“noun”)
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 and a rhema (“verb”), as Plato’s Sophist informs us: fragments (B 2 and 50 D-K, cited in Diels/Kranz 1968: from the combination of rhemata and onomata arises 151 and 161) suggest that logos means something that the “first interweaving”, the “first and smallest of the structures the physis. This may be conceived as a meta- logoi” (Sophist 262c). An ancient encyclopaedia entry – physical “sense” that emerges in “speech” (Vassallo the 100th of the pseudo-Platonic Definitions – explains 2020), or as “measure” that determines the balance and logos as a “voice in signs that can name every single being” good arrangement of the world, which is characterised (Horoi 414d). A restriction mentioned in the Theaetetus by opposites but divinely directed (Long 2009). Possibly suggests that in Plato’s time, too, logos was understood Heraclitus’ use of logos indicates that the world reveals as speech communicated vocally. Socrates describes itself as an ordered and intelligible whole (Johnstone “(discursive) thinking” (dianoeisthai) as a logos, which 2014: 21). (For an overview of how translators have the “soul” “goes through” with itself; likewise, “thinking” rendered the word logos in Heraclitus’ fragments over (doxa) is a logos, which someone does not address to the last two centuries, see Gianvittorio 2010: 158 f.). another with his voice, but silently to himself (Theaetetus While Heraclitus uses logos mainly in the singular, 189e–190a). the Sophists emphasise the plurality of logoi, There are numerous expressions derived from logos “pro-positions”, “speeches” or “arguments”, which and legein. The adjective logikos, for example, is the can contradict each other. In this respect, the title of the origin of the word “logic”, derived from logike techne: anonymous tract Dissoi logoi, “Twofold logoi”, is striking, “the art concerning logoi and thinking”. Logos is found as it is intended to make various methods of argumen- in compound words such as “logotherapy” or “dialogue”. tation comprehensible by means of pairs of opposites Abstract terms derived in accordance with the original (Becker/Scholz 2004). This text, which was probably schema theo-logos (“one who talks about the gods/god”) written at the turn of the fifth and fourth centuries B.C., designate many sciences, for instance (in the context of is often associated with the relativism of Protagoras. the observation of nature) key terms such as “biology” Protagoras’ logos that man is the measure of all things or “cosmology”. is familiar to us from Plato’s Theaetetus, where it is discussed at length (151e ff.; Schiappa 2003: 117–133). The claim “to make the weaker logos the stronger” is 2. Early Greek philosophy: logos as cosmic probably the best-known statement on logos associated principle and Sophistic practices of logoi with the Sophists, the “wisdom teachers”, and the In the surviving fragments of the Early Greek thinkers rhetoric teachers of the fifth century B.C.; Aristotle dealing with physis, “nature” (see Dunshirn 2019), the describes it in the Rhetoric as the “promise” of Protagoras word logos is most conspicuously encountered in (Rhetoric II, 24, 1402a23 f.) (For an appreciation of the Heraclitus. “With regard to logos, being – always – men Sophists, see Schirren/Zinsmaier 2003: 10–30.) prove to be uncomprehending”, is the beginning of the piece traditionally counted as fragment 1 (Fragment B 1 3. Plato: the true logos of the world soul D-K, cited in Diels/Kranz 1968: 150). Aristotle already points out the difficulty of understanding the word order In Plato’s dialogues which criticize rhetoric, several in this sentence. It is unclear what the word “always” (aei) reflections on the sophistic technique of logoi can be refers to (Rhetoric III, 5, 1407b14–18). It could specify found. The true art of oratory must not be a persua- the aforementioned logos as being “always” – in which sive technique independent of knowledge, it has to try case the way is paved for the interpretation of the logos to bring about the good with a constant view to what as a cosmic principle; or “always” defines in more detail is just (Gorgias 504d–e); if not, an orator acts merely the lack of understanding of people who never under- on the basis of his experience and creates pleasure in the stand the logos. audience, but is of no use to them (Gorgias 462c–463d). It is disputed whether Heraclitus at this point aims A feature that distinguishes real from apparent with logos at a world law at all or does not instead refer knowledge is the ability to give a logos of it, the famous to his own “account” (Guthrie 1985: 419–425; Röd logon didonai, “to give an account” (Wieland 1999: 247– 1988: 97–100; Johnstone 2014). Further Heraclitus 250; Weiner 2012). In Plato’s Phaedo, Socrates reports Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 2
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 that he fled into the logoi in order to “spot” the truth in of “justified true belief” (where “justified” renders the them; through this flight, he wanted to avoid “becoming words “with logos”), and was intensively discussed in blind” in his soul when trying to comprehend the world connexion with the Gettier problem (that a justified and with his senses (Phaedo 99d–e; Beierwaltes 2011: 79 f.). true opinion can also happen to be true) (Gettier 1963; The philosophers, unlike the (court) orators whose Schukraft 2017). speaking time is limited, have leisure to pursue the The Eleatic Stranger explicitly addresses the truth and diverse logoi they get involved in (Theaetetus 172c–e). falsity of logoi in Plato’s Sophist, where the sentences In Plato’s dialogues, Socrates proves to be a prominent “Theaetetus sits” and “Theaetetus flies” function as figure in assessing whether individual logoi are tenable examples of the “smallest logos” (263a; Lorenz/Mit- or not. In the Theaetetus, Socrates reveals his “midwifery” telstrass 1966). In connection with the question of (maieutike), a conversational technique that refers to the non-being and being, the discussants define logos – as “birthing souls” and their productions, the logoi (150b; mentioned above under “linguistic” – as the “linking” of Sedley 2004: 28–37; Futter 2018). Through Socrates’ onoma and rhema, of “noun” and “verb” or “subject” intervention, his interlocutors get into aporias, situa- and “predicate” (262c, a passage with which overviews tions where they cannot get through to what they are of grammatical theory often begin, cf. Jungen/Lohn- looking for. In the process, however, they determine stein 2007: 36 f.; on the danger of the non-being of which logoi do not lead to a solution of the problem in logos see König 2020: 449 f.). The rhema is an “indication” question (Erler 1987). In the Theaetetus, for example, (deloma) of actions, the onoma a “sign” (semeion) several attempts are made to determine episteme, attached to those who perform the actions (262a; the “understanding of something” or “knowledge”. The Heidegger 1992: 590–592; on the relation of onoma interlocutors do not arrive at a satisfactory definition. and logos in the Seventh Letter see Liatsi 2008; on the They also reject the last attempt to define knowledge question of the “rightness” of the onomata, the as “true opinion (doxa) with logos” (Theaetetus 201c–d). “names”, see Sedley 2003; Enache 2007). The inter- This definition seems insufficient to the dialogue’s part- locutors in Plato’s dialogues, however, do not only ners, among other reasons, because logos, understood comment on whether various logoi are true or false, as an enumeration of the constituent parts or as an they often let the argument or speech itself become the indication of the essential characteristics of a thing, is subject in their conversations. Thus, the (present) already contained in the opinion of it or the “belief”, logos, the momentary conversation, may be said to the doxa (206c–210b; Gill 2003: 167–169). “force” them to do something, it “flees” from them, it In general, logos is said to belong to both doxa and “conceals itself” and much more (Dunshirn 2010: 129– episteme, or “knowledge” (on Plato’s conception of 142). opinion and knowledge see Burnyeat 1980; Fine 1990; Of particular relevance for natural philosophy are the Graeser 1991). According to the Platonic view, however, different logoi that arise when the divine “craftsman”, opinion and knowledge refer to their contents in varying the Demiurge, arranges the world, as Plato’s Timaeus degrees of objectivity (Szaif 2017). In a view of the world tells us. In forming the psyche of the world, that which based solely on opinion, we easily get confused; things “animates” the cosmos, the divine world-builder that we think are large in one context turn out to be “mixes together” a “third form” of being from the small the next time we look at them (Republic 523c– “nature” of the “same” and the “different” (Timaeus 524d). Only with knowledge, which determines the 34b–35c). Out of all three, he forms two opposing orbits, factual connections in orientation to the ideas, do we namely a rotation of identity and a circle of difference arrive at permanently true statements. With reference (which can be understood as the – from the point of to the different objects of thinking and knowing, one view of the earth – opposing movements of the starry can therefore speak of an (epistemic) two-world theory sky and the planets). In its connection with the world in Plato (Strobel 2017: 360–362). However, the above- body, the world soul produces logoi that correspond mentioned attempted definition from the Theaetetus – to these rotations, of course without “sound and episteme as “true opinion with logos” – established noise” (37b). These logoi give rise, firstly, to “opinions” itself as the classical definition of knowledge in the form (doxai) – deriving from the circulation of the “other” and Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 3
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 referring to the perceptible – and, secondly, to “convic- we come across passages in Plato on the “effectiveness tion” (pistis), or – in the case of the circulation of the of speech” (Hetzel 2011), of the logos as a “mighty “same” and with reference to the faculty of thought – ruler”, as Gorgias calls it in his Encomium of Helena to “reason” (nous) and “knowledge” (episteme) (37b–c; (Fragment B 11, 8 D-K, cited in Diels/Kranz 1964: 290; Karfik 2004: 174–201; Karfik 2020). on the drama allusions in Gorgias see Novokhatko A comparable listing of cognitive powers is found in the 2020: 86–91). Thus, in Plato’s Charmides, the logoi with analogy of the divided line in the Republic, which offers Socrates turn out to be the true remedy for Charmides’ evidence for logos in the sense of “relation”. Socrates’ malaise, since it is they that bring about prudence audience is asked to imagine a line divided into sections (Charmides 157a–b; Derrida [1972] 1981: 124 f.). of different lengths and then to “cut” the imagined line In view of the above-mentioned passages in the “in the same logos”, in identical proportion (Republic Timaeus and the Republic, where mythos and logos 509d). Entities of different degrees of being as well as occur in close connection, a strict separation of these the “affections of the soul” corresponding to them are terms in the sense of the opposition of the irrational assigned to the four segments of the line: “imagination” and the rational, as suggested by influential overviews (eikasia), “conviction” (pistis), “thinking” (dianoia) and (Nestle 1940), seems problematic. Rather, a separation “reasoning” (noesis); these participate in truth to an within the spoken – whether it be called mythos or increasing degree (511d–e; Erler 2007: 399–401). In this logos – in terms of the degrees of being seems appro- respect, it is appropriate to speak of “levels of truth” priate: a logos or mythos can be about insights of rea- (Janke 2007: 122), especially since the Greek word son, concerned with the “perfect” being, or assump- alethes (“true”, “truthful”) is capable of an increase. tions of opinion, concerned with the “in-between”, the Thus Plato may speak of someone having said some- simultaneously existing and non-existing (Republic thing “truer” or “in a truer way” (Gorgias 493d) or of 477a–478e; cf. Timaeus 27d–28a; Strobel 2017: 360 f.). the interlocutors having (supposedly) found the “truest” logos, the most accurate definition, of something 4. Aristotle: man and logos (Theaetetus 208b, cf. Cratylus 438c). At the peak of knowledge, the logos may be suspended. In Plato’s Aristotle’s differentiation of episteme (“knowledge”), Symposium, it is said that at the climax of the ascension doxa (“opinion”), pistis (“conviction”) and phantasia of knowledge, a “nature of wondrous beauty” is (“imagination”) can be compared with the gradation of glimpsed. This no longer appears as a body, nor in the the soul’s abilities in the Platonic analogy of the divided manner of the previous forms of knowledge or logos. line. This differentiation is based not least on having What emerges is an “absolute, separate, simple and or not having logos. It is central to Aristotle’s natural everlasting” beauty (cf. Symposium 210e–211b; Sier philosophy, anthropology and ethics (Rese 2003). 1997: 285 f.). According to Aristotle’s Politics, the only living being who Explaining the arrangement of the world, Plato’s has logos is man (Politics I, 2, 1253a9 f.). How does this character Timaeus speaks of an eikos mythos (Timaeus logos-having distinguish him from other living things? 29d) as well as of an eikos logos (30b; Brisson 2012), i.e. For Aristotle, logoi are also the expression of opinion of a “likely” or “probable” “story” or “speech” (on the (doxa) and the convictions (pisteis) that go with it, as interpretative tradition of eikos see Martijn 2010: 219– well as of nous, “reason”. As is evident from De anima 235). In the Republic, Socrates repeatedly points out to (“On the Soul”), these processes of the soul are peculiar his interlocutors that they produce the “good city” they to man (De anima III, 3). Together with man, other living are talking about “through the logos” (472de) or that beings have perception, some of them also have phan- they “tell it as myth” (mythologoumen logo, 501e). In tasia (“imagination”, De anima 428a10). As Aristotle the latter instance, the word logos appears to enter explains in the Posterior Analytics, the opinion of human into opposition with ergon, the “work” or “deed”: until beings is concerned with “the true and the false”, with the philosophers obtain power, there is no end to evils, that which may be otherwise (Posterior Analytics I, 33, and the constitution put forward in conversation does 89a2 f.). The faculties which always speak truth, i.e. not “actually” (ergo) reach its goal (501e). Nevertheless, reason and knowledge (De anima III, 3, 428a17 f.), deal Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 4
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 with contents that cannot be otherwise (Posterior 5. The Stoic universal logos Analytics I, 33, 88b31 f.; on the connection between reason, knowledge and logos see Bronstein 2016: 58). Probably the most influential concept of logos – at least For the realm of action, according to Aristotle, the in terms of natural philosophy – is that of the Stoa. orientation towards orthos logos, the “right reason” In particular, the representatives of the Ancient Stoa that simultaneously prescribes and explains something, are regarded as proponents of the world logos, which is central (Nicomachean Ethics II, 2, 1103b31-34; Moss determines all phenomena and developments in the 2014; Frede 2020: 409 f.). The virtue or “excellence” cosmos (Kahn 1969). For the Stoics, two principles can (arete) of man is the disposition or “having” associated be regarded as components of the universe, namely with the right logos (hexis, Nicomachean Ethics VI, 13, that which is acted upon and that which acts (SVF II 300; 1144b26 f.). cf. Long/Sedley 1987: 268 f./Fragment 44B). The former Those writings of Aristotle which were later can be termed matter, the latter as the logos working summarised under the name “Organon” deal with parts in it, that is, the divine reason. The Stoics also refer to of sentences, negations and the connectedness of logoi this as God, as the “fate” (heimarmene) or as logos, in conclusions. They had a decisive influence on the according to which everything is carried out (SVF II Western conception of speech and thought for centuries. 915 = Arnim 2004, vol. 2: 264). According to Diogenes Aristotle discusses various types of logoi that “indicate” Laërtius, the world-reason is conceived by Zeno, the (semainein) something. An indicating logos is not always founder of the Stoic school, and by his successor “declarative” (apophantikos) in the sense of “true” or Chrysippus as “seminal principle”, as logos spermatikos, “false”; this is evident in the case of logos as prayer or which encompasses the germ of everything; this principle request (On Interpretation 4, 16b26–17a5). Of course, the as primordial fire brings forth everything and makes the focus of Aristotle’s analyses is on the logos apophantikos, matter in which it is inherent “serviceable” for further “declarative speech”. Here, “affirmation” (kataphasis) becoming and creates the four elements (Diogenes is to be distinguished from “negation” (apophasis, On Laërtius VII, 135 f. = SVF I 102; cf. Long/Sedley 1987: Interpretation 5, 17a8 f.; Wey 2014). Universal affirma- 275/Fragment 46B; further passages in Arnim 2004, tive or negative (with some qualifications, also particular vol. 4: 91–93). Here, just like matter, logos is under- affirmative or negative) propositions can be regarded stood as something corporeal, since according to the as elements of syllogisms, of “conclusions”. These indi- Stoics something incorporeal cannot effect anything cate – linked via a finite number of middle terms – the (SVF II 363; cf. Long/Sedley 1987: 272/Fragment 45B). cause of certain facts (Detel 2005: 21–30). The active principle, just like the suffering principle, An essential function, which is also highly relevant is uncreated and imperishable, in contrast to all the in natural philosophy, is assigned to logos in Aristotle’s elements of the cosmos, which perish in the cyclically considerations of physis and ousia, of “beingness” or “sub- occurring conflagration (SVF II 299; cf. Long/Sedley stance”, as documented in his Physics and Metaphysics 1987: 268 f./Fragment 44B). Everything is completely (Wiplinger 1971). In the list of the four ways in which rationally determined by the universal logos. A quote cause is spoken of, logos is found in the explanation by Chrysippus preserved by Plutarch emphasises that in of the second type of cause, eidos (the “form”): this is the world not even the smallest part can come into being “the logos of what-it-was-to-be and its genera” – logos in any other way than according to the “common nature” functions here as the “explanatory speech” of ti en einai, and according to its logos (Plutarch, On Stoic Self- of “what-it-was-to-be” or the “creative concept of being” Contradictions 1050B–D = SVF II 937; cf. Long/Sedley (Prantl 1997: 211; Höffe 2006: 173). In this logos of 1987: 331/Fragment 54T). The logos can be conceived definition, reason grasps the universal (to katholou) as a “structural plan” according to which nature is active about a thing (Tugendhat 2003: 15–17), for example, the (Löbl 1986: 64). According to Cicero’s discussion of characterisation of the human being as a “two-footed Chrysippus’ view, all things in the cosmos came into animal” (Aristotle, Metaphysics IV, 4, 1006a31–b4; being because of another thing and are imperfect; the Horn 2005: 330 f.; on the problem of defining ousia, world alone comprises everything and is therefore “beingness” or “substance”, as logos see Weiner 2016). perfect – there is “nothing more perfect” than the Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 5
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 world (Cicero, De natura deorum II, 14, 37–39; cf. SVF II providence, there are evils, a complex explanation by 641 = Arnim 2004, vol. 2: 193 f.). Cicero encountered Chrysippus has come down to us: the good is opposed to similar views in Panaetius, who emphasised the harmo- the evil; good and evil must exist together and mutually nious structure of the world and in particular the unity support each other, since no concept of the opposite of the human organism. Everything in man is designed exists without that to which it is opposed. Moreover, in in the best way for him to recognise the divine and the nature, unfavourable things have arisen as a “con- beauty in the world (Cicero, De natura deorum II, 54– comitance” (parakolouthesis): the physical arrangement 56, 133–141; Pohlenz 1959: 196 f.; Capelle 1954: 51 f.). of the human head, for example, is highly conducive to Several times in the expositions of Stoic doctrines, the increase of its reason, but it also entails the thin logos is also encountered in the plural. The doxographer bone of the skull which is susceptible to injury (SVF II Aëtius reports that the god of the Stoics encompasses 1169 f.; cf. Long/Sedley 1987: 329 f./Fragment 54Q; the logoi spermatikoi, the seminal principles, according on the development of the “theodicy” in the Stoa, see to which everything happens fatefully. At the same Zeller 2006: 176–182, cf. Steinmetz 1994: 610–612). time, Aëtius points out the unifying nature of the logos. The problem of determinism, which arose from the As a deity endowed with reason, the logos acts like an divine determination of the world’s fate and seemed to “intelligent, designing fire” that runs through the entire rule out free action, is answered in the Stoa with the cosmos and takes on different names depending on the argument that the “perfect cause” for actions lies with substance in which it works (Aëtius I, 7, 33 = SVF II man (SVF II 974/Arnim 2004, vol. 2: 282 f.), namely his 1027; cf. Long/Sedley 1987: 274 f./Fragment 46A). This logos, his reason. The “presentations” (phantasiai) that active force is often called “breath” (pneuma) or arise through external influences and provide the “breathy substance”: it gives the bodies their cohesion material for cognition are merely contributory causes (SVF II 439; cf. Long/Sedley 1987: 282/Fragment 47F), to which man must first give his assent (synkatathesis) which is conceived as “tension” (tonos). In the twofold in order for them to trigger an impulse for action form of the “tensile movement” that goes along with (Steinmetz 1994: 611; Schriefl 2019: 114–118). To live it, the dynamics of world events become apparent: according to the universal logos and “in agreement” directed outwards, the tensile movement endows sizes (homologumenos) with the physis does not mean that and properties, directed inwards, unity and substance man is unfree because of predestination, but that he (SVF II 451; cf. Long/Sedley 1987: 283/Fragment 47J). reaches the highest perfection (SVF I 179; cf. Long/ On the basis of such testimonies, the Stoic concep- Sedley 1987: 394/Fragment 63B). tion of the world has been characterised as monistic In the Stoic tradition, as with Aristotle, man’s parti- (see e.g. Steinmetz 1994: 606 f.) and pantheistic (see cipation in logos is regarded as a feature distinguishing Zeller’s influential account of the “Stoic system” in him from other living beings (SVF I 515/Arnim 2004, intellectual history, Zeller 2006: 118; for general discussion vol. 1: 116). In the Latin testimonies of the Stoic doctrines, of pantheism see Bollacher 2020). “Everything is inter- logos is conceived as ratio. In De natura deorum, Cicero twined” and forms a “sacred connection” that leads to quotes Chrysippus’ statement that there is ratio an order in “the same cosmos”, says Marcus Aurelius – (“reason”) only in man, beyond which nothing can rise who in this context speaks of the “one cosmos” that (De natura deorum II, 6, 16 = SVF II 1012; cf. Long/ consists of everything, the “one God” that works through Sedley 1987: 324 f./Fragment 54E). Sextus Empiricus everything, and the “one logos” that is common to all makes the argument more specifically: man does not rational living beings (Marcus Aurelius, Meditations VII, distinguish himself from the alogical creatures by the 9). In connection with the necessity of natural pro- prophorikos logos, the “speech suitable for utterance”, cesses, which is understood as “fate” (heimarmene), the but by the endiathetos logos, the “speech set within” Stoics also speak of “providence” (pronoia) (Medita- (Adversus mathematicos VIII, 275 = SVF II 135/Arnim tions XII, 14; on Chrysippus’ view of providence, see e.g. 2004, vol. 2: 43). This distinction between a logos Plutarch, On Stoic Self-Contradictions 1044E–F = SVF II directed outwards (like animal sounds) and an internal 1160/Arnim 2004, vol. 2: 334). On the question of why, logos (like reason) can be traced back to the time of the if the world and human affairs are governed by dispute between the Stoics of the second century B.C. Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 6
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 and the Platonist Carneades on the question of “speech act” also resounds: “And God said, Let there be whether other living beings also had logos (Pohlenz light” (Genesis 1:3; Hetzel 2011: 370–376). Tradition- 1959: 39; Kamesar 2004: 163 f.). This question will ally, logos in the prologue of John’s Gospel is translated become important for theological speculation in the as “word”, which obviously does not mean a single Roman imperial period, as it is explored in Philon of word but the divine verbum as a “empowered word” Alexandria. (Bühner/Verbeke 1980: 499), a speech to which great power is attributed. In theology, in connection with the divine logos that turns to the world, there is talk of the 6. Theology of logos in the Imperial period “event of Jesus Christ” (Bultmann 1993: 288 f.). This In Philo’s allegorical interpretation of biblical stories, logos is the “creating” and “healing” speech (ibid. 268– Moses represents the logos endiathetos and Aaron the 274): In the Old Testament, the word of God is heard, logos prophorikos. While the latter’s pronouncements which brings forth and creates heaven and earth and all communicate the contents of Moses’ revelation to the that is (Schlier 1974: 417–419). The healing effect of the people, God speaks “in” Moses, whose spirit is in contact divine logos is expressed, for example, in the words of with the Lord (Quod deterius 126 f.; Kamesar 2004: 164). prayer in the liturgy of the Mass, which take up the New Similarly to the Stoics, Philo views the logos as a divine Testament: “But only say the word (eipe logo), and my agency, though his concept of logos is a highly complex soul shall be healed” (cf. Matthew 8:8; Luke 7:7; on the one (Lévy 2018). Philon also speaks of spermatikos logos, hearing of the “revelation” in the “Word” of God, which the “seminal principle” that guarantees a rational defines our being, see Rahner 1997: 16 f.). development of everything that becomes (Legum allego- In his interpretation of the logos of Christ (for a riae III, 150; Verbeke 1980: 485 f.). For the subsequent collection of passages, see Balthasar 1991: 95–216), the Christian doctrine of logos, the role that Philo ascribes early Christian theologian Origen refers to the distinction to the logos as God’s attention to the world is of partic- between the logos prophorikos and the logos endiathetos, ular importance (Löhr 2010: 354; Burz-Tropper 2014: the “speech suitable for utterance” and the “speech set 102 f.). Among other things, Philo calls the logos the within”, mentioned above in connection with the Stoic “first-born son” of God (De agricultura 51; Löhr 2010: logos concept. Origen maintains that neither type of 348); he regards logos as the combination of God’s logos, as expressions of human reason, can grasp the power and goodness (Pohlenz 1959: 373–375; Hadas- divine logos (Contra Celsum VI, 65). Porphyry makes Lebel 2012: 186–188; Niehoff 2018: 217–223). use of this in his polemic against the logos of Christ, Christian thinkers clearly relied on this concept when which he argues is not a logos at all (Ramelli 2012: 334– they started to understand Christ, the second person in 336; on the interpretation of logos in Origen see Gögler the divine Trinity, as logos (Menke 2009). The doctrine 1963: 244–281). of Christ as the “Word” (logos) emerging from God can A synopsis and critique of the various ancient accounts already be found in early Christian authors, such as of logos in non-Christian philosophy and in Gnosticism can Justin Martyr in the second century AD (Apologia prima be found in Plotinus (Brisson 1999). In his treatise On pro Christianis 23; Hünermann 2009). The central New Providence (Enneads III, 2–3), Plotinus criticises both a Testament text for Christian logos theology is the view of the world that attributes everything to the prologue of John’s Gospel: En arche en ho logos, kai ho coincidental meeting of atoms or the separation of logos en pros ton theon, kai theos en ho logos, “In the various primordial substances and the Stoic teaching beginning was the logos, and the logos was with God, that the cosmos is determined down to the last detail and God was the logos”. (The traces of the “Wisdom by a divine logos. In this case, there would only be the Literature” in John’s prologue – i.e. the theological divine; “we” would be “nothing” (III, 2, 9). Similarly, the speculations reflected e.g. in the biblical books of Job, view of the followers of Aristotle’s doctrine that divine Ecclesiastes or Proverbs – are explained by Lips 1990: reason only refers to the celestial spheres and not to 290–317 and Burz-Tropper 2014). These words echo the sublunary world, i.e. the four spheres below the the beginning of Genesis, where it says: Bereshit bara moon, namely fire, air, water and earth (as the centre elochim …, “In the beginning God created …”. There the of the world in the geocentric worldview), must be Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 7
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 rejected. Instead, according to Plotinus, divine providence the fact that, especially in the 20th century, a fundamental extends to everything, nothing is not subject to its care; critique of so-called logocentrism was formulated. Under the universe depends on nous, the “spirit” (III, 2, 6). this heading, Ludwig Klages, for example, criticises a However, Plotinus does not understand the logos as a rationality that is hostile to life and which tethers it deity, like the Stoa, which as a physical force completely to mind, and Jacques Derrida – giving “logocentric” a determines worldly events. Rather, logos “flows out” of completely different meaning – criticises a conception nous, “reason” (emanation); through logos, reason acts of the sign that determines the entire tradition of on matter: “For that which flows out of the spirit is European philosophy and systematically favours logos, and it always flows out of it as long as the spirit spoken language over written language as a medium of is present in the things being” (III, 2, 2). This logos is the cognition (Pöhler 1980). unfolding of the one, single reason into the material world consisting of many parts (Halfwassen 2004: 17). Basic literature In this multiplicity of logos, one reason for the (apparent) evil and unhappiness in the world is to be sought. Unlike Aall, Anathon 1968: Der Logos. Geschichte seiner Ent- nous, which is always in complete unity with itself, the wickelung in der griechischen Philosophie und der logos that “comes” from it neither exists everywhere in christlichen Litteratur. 2 Bände. Unveränderter Nach- its full form nor does it “give itself in its entirety to those druck der Ausgabe Leipzig 1896–1899. Frankfurt/M., to whom it gives itself” (III, 2, 16). It sets the parts of the Minerva. world in opposition to each other and brings them forth Bühner, Jahn-Adolf/Verbeke, Gérard 1980: Logos. In: as deficient, from which war and struggles result (ibid.). Ritter, Joachim/Gründer, Karlfried (eds): Historisches Plotinus also speaks of logos in the Heraclitean sense Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Band 5: L–Mn. Darmstadt, as the unity of opposites. The essence of logos is to Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: col. 491–502. embrace differences (ibid.; Motta 2019). Johnstone, Mark A. 2014: On ‘logos’ in Heraclitus. In: At the end of antiquity, Proclus accentuates the Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47: 1–29. relationship between the One (hen) and logos in his Kelber, Wilhelm 1986: Die Logoslehre. Von Heraklit bis synopsis of the positions of various “Platonists” concern- Origenes. Frankfurt/M., Fischer. ing the hypostases, the levels of being or emanation of Löhr, Winrich 2010: Logos. In: Schöllgen, Georg/Brak- concretely existing things (on the hierarchy of the logoi mann, Heinzgerd/de Blaauw, Sible/Fuhrer, Therese/ in Proclus in connection with his philosophy of nature Hoheisel, Karl/Löhr, Winrich/Speyer, Wolfgang/ see Martijn 2010: 235–239). If there were no One, there Thraede, Klaus (eds): Reallexikon für Antike und would be neither knowledge (gnosis) nor logos: “For Christentum. Sachwörterbuch zur Auseinanderset- logos too is one out of many, if it is perfect” (Theologia zung des Christentums mit der antiken Welt. Platonica II, 1; see Saffrey/Westerink 1974, vol. 2: 8, line Band 23. Stuttgart, Hiersemann: 327–435. 20 f.). This clearly expresses the connection between Rowe, Christopher J. 2003: Logos. In: Hornblower, Si- One, Being, cognition and language, but at the same mon/Spawforth, Antony (eds): The Oxford Classical time the difference between One and logos: The One is Dictionary. Third Edition Revised. Oxford, Oxford “not yet” logos whereas Being is “already” logos (II, 2; University Press: 882–882. see Saffrey/Westerink 1974, vol. 2: 21, line 12 f). Literature 7. Outlook Aall, Anathon 1968: Der Logos. Geschichte seiner The various ancient concepts of logos have taken on Entwickelung in der griechischen Philosophie und enormous significance in the subsequent history of der christlichen Litteratur. 2 Bände. Unveränderter European thought. This can be seen, for example, in the Nachdruck der Ausgabe Leipzig 1896–1899. Frank- fact that the first “International Journal for the Philosophy furt/M., Minerva. of Culture” in Germany, founded in 1910, was named Aëtius 2020: Aëtiana V. An Edition of the Reconstructed “Logos” (see Becker et al. 2020). It is also reflected in Text of the Placita with a Commentary and a Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 8
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 Collection of Related Texts. Edited by Jaap Mansfeld übrigen urchristlichen Literatur. Fünfte, verbesserte and David Runia. Leiden, Brill. und stark vermehrte Auflage. Berlin, Töpelmann. Aristotle: De anima = Aristoteles 2011: Über die Seele. Becker, Alexander/Scholz, Peter (eds) 2004: Dissoi Logoi. Griechisch/Deutsch. Übersetzt und herausgegeben Zweierlei Ansichten. Ein sophistischer Traktat. Text – von Gernot Krapinger. Stuttgart, Reclam. Übersetzung – Kommentar. Berlin, Akademie Verlag. Aristotle: Metaphysics = Aristotle 1989: Metaphysik. Becker, Ralf/Bermes, Christian/Westerkamp, Dirk (eds) Neubearbeitung der Übersetzung von Hermann Bo- 2020: Zeitschrift für Kulturphilosophie, Schwerpunkt: nitz. Mit Einleitung und Kommentar herausgegeben LOGOS. Zeitschrift für Kulturphilosophie 14 (2). von Horst Seidl. Griechischer Text in der Edition von Beekes, Robert 2010: Etymological Dictionary of Greek. Wilhelm Christ. Griechisch-Deutsch. 2 Bände. 3., With the Assistance of Lucien van Beek. Volume 1. verbesserte Auflage. Hamburg, Meiner. Leiden, Brill. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics = Aristotle 2008: Nikoma- Beierwaltes, Werner 2011: Deus est veritas. Zur Rezep- chische Ethik. Übersetzt und herausgegeben von Ur- tion des griechischen Wahrheitsbegriffes in der früh- sula Wolf. 2. Auflage. Reinbek bei Hamburg, Rowohlt. christlichen Theologie. In: Beierwaltes, Werner (ed.): Aristotle: On Interpretation = Aristotle 1973: The Cate- Fußnoten zu Plato. Frankfurt/M., Klostermann: 77–97. gories. On Interpretation. With an English Trans- Boeder, Heribert 1959: Der frühgriechische Wort- lation by Harold P. Cooke. Prior Analytics. With an gebrauch von Logos und Aletheia. In: Archiv für English Translation by Hugh Tredennick. Reprint. Begriffsgeschichte 4: 82–112. Cambridge/MA, Harvard University Press. Bollacher, Martin 2020: Pantheism. In: Kirchhoff, Aristotle: Organon = Aristotle 1997–1998: Organon. Thomas (ed.): Online Encyclopedia Philosophy Herausgegeben, übersetzt, mit Einleitungen und of Nature / Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie. Anmerkungen versehen von Hans Günter Zekl. Heidelberg, Universitätsbibliothek Heidelberg: Griechisch-Deutsch. 4 Bände. Hamburg, Meiner. https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2020.0.76525. Aristotle: Physik = Aristotle 1987–1988: Physik. Vorlesung Brisson, Luc 1999: Logos et logoi chez Plotin. Leur über die Natur. Übersetzt, mit einer Einleitung und nature et leur role. In: Les cahiers philosophiques de mit Anmerkungen herausgegeben von Hans Günter Strasbourg 8: 87–108. Zekl. Griechisch-Deutsch. 2 Bände. Hamburg, Meiner. Brisson, Luc 2012: Why is the Timaeus called an eikôs Aristotle: Politics = Aristotle 2012: Politik. Übersetzt und muthos and an eikôs logos? In: Collobert, Catherine/ mit einer Einleitung sowie Anmerkungen herausge- Destrée, Pierre/Gonzalez, Francisco J. (eds): Plato geben von Eckart Schütrumpf. Hamburg, Meiner. and Myth. Studies on the Use and Status of Platonic Aristotle: Posterior Analytics = Aristotle 1998: Erste Myths. Leiden, Brill: 369–391. Analytik. Zweite Analytik. Herausgegeben, übersetzt, Bronstein, David 2016: Aristotle on Knowledge and mit Einleitungen und Anmerkungen versehen von Learning. The Posterior Analytics. Oxford, Oxford Hans Günter Zekl. Griechisch-deutsch. Hamburg, University Press. Meiner. Buchheim, Thomas (ed.) 1989: Gorgias von Leontinoi, Aristotle: Rhetorik = Aristotle 2006: The “Art” of Rhetoric. Reden, Fragmente und Testimonien. Griechisch- With an English Translation by John H. Freese. Reprint. deutsch. Hamburg, Meiner. Cambridge/MA, Harvard University Press. Bühner, Jahn-Adolf/Verbeke, Gérard 1980: Logos. In: Arnim, Hans von (ed.) 2004: Stoicorum veterum frag- Ritter, Joachim/Gründer, Karlfried (eds): Historisches menta. Volumen I–IV. Editio stereotypa editionis Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Band 5: L–Mn. Darm- primae [1905–1924]. München, Saur. stadt, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: col. 491– Balthasar, Hans Urs von (ed.) 1991: Origenes, Geist und 502. Feuer. Ein Aufbau aus seinen Schriften. 3. Auflage. Bultmann, Rudolf 1993: Der Begriff des Wortes Gottes Einsiedeln, Johannes. im Neuen Testament. In: Bultmann, Rudolf: Glauben Bauer, Walter 1958: Griechisch-deutsches Wörterbuch und Verstehen. Gesammelte Aufsätze. Erster Band. zu den Schriften des Neuen Testaments und der Neunte Auflage. Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck: 268–293. Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 9
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 Burnyeat, Myles F. 1980: Socrates and the jury. Para- schaft unter Mitwirkung zahlreicher Fachgelehrter doxes in Plato’s distinction between knowledge and bearbeitet. Band 3: Iuppiter–Nasidienus. München, true belief. In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Soci- Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag: 710–715. ety, Supplementary Volume 54: 173–191. Dörrie, Heinrich/Baltes, Matthias 1996 (eds): Der Platonis- Burz-Tropper, Veronika 2014: Weisheitliche Traditionen mus in der Antike. Grundlagen – System – Entwicklung. im Johannesprolog revisited. In: Protokolle zur Bibel Band 4: Die philosophische Lehre des Platonismus. 23 (2): 83–106. Einige grundlegende Axiome/Platonische Physik (im Capelle, Wilhelm 1954: Geschichte der Philosophie IV. antiken Verständnis). I. Bausteine 101–124. Stuttgart, Die griechische Philosophie. Vierter Teil: Von der Alten Frommann-Holzboog. Stoa bis zum Eklektizismus im 1. Jahrhundert v. Chr. Dunshirn, Alfred 2010: Logos bei Platon als Spiel und Zweite, stark erweiterte Auflage. Berlin, de Gruyter. Ereignis. Würzburg, Königshausen & Neumann. Cassirer, Ernst [1923] 1973: Philosophie der symboli- Dunshirn, Alfred 2019: Physis [English version]. In: schen Formen. Erster Teil: Die Sprache. 6., unverän- Kirchhoff, Thomas (eds): Online Encyclopedia Philo- derte Auflage. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Buch- sophy of Nature / Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie. gesellschaft. Heidelberg, Universitätsbibliothek Heidelberg: Cassirer, Ernst 1953: The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. https://doi.org/10.11588/oepn.2019.0.66404. Vol. 1: Language. New Haven, Yale University Press. Enache, Cătălin 2007: Orthotes. Die Idee der Sprach- Castoriadis, Cornelius 1990: Gesellschaft als imaginäre vertikalität von Homer bis zur Stoa mit besonderer Institution. Entwurf einer politischen Philosophie. Rücksicht auf Platons Kratylos. Dissertation, Univer- Übersetzt von Horst Brühmann. Frankfurt/M., Suhr- sität Wien. kamp. Erler, Michael 1987: Der Sinn der Aporien in den Dialo- Cicero: De natura deorum = Cicero 2000: De natura de- gen Platons. Übungsstücke zur Anleitung im philoso- orum. With an English Translation by Harris Rackham. phischen Denken. Berlin, de Gruyter. Reprint. Cambridge/MA, Harvard University Press. Erler, Michael 2007: Platon. Basel, Schwabe. Denyer, Nicholas 1991: Language, Thought and False- Fattal, Michel 2005: Ricerche sul logos. Da Omero a Plotino. hood in Ancient Greek Philosophy. London, Routledge. A cura di Roberto Radice. Milano, Vita e Pensiero. Derrida, Jacques 1981: Dissemination. Translated, with Fine, Gail 1990: Knowledge and belief in Republic V–VII. an Introduction and Additional Notes, by Barbara In: Everson, Stephen (ed.): Epistemology. Cambridge, Johnson. London, Athlone. Cambridge University Press: 85–115. Detel, Wolfgang 2005: Aristoteles. Leipzig, Reclam. Flatscher, Matthias 2011: Logos und Lethe. Zur phäno- Diels, Hermann/Kranz, Walther (eds) 1964: Die Fragmente menologischen Sprachauffassung im Spätwerk von der Vorsokratiker. Griechisch und deutsch. Zweiter Heidegger und Wittgenstein. Freiburg, Alber. Band. 11. Auflage, unveränderter Nachdruck der 6. Forschner, Maximilian 2018: Die Philosophie der Stoa. Auflage. Zürich, Weidmann. Logik, Physik und Ethik. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Diels, Hermann/Kranz, Walther (eds) 1968: Die Fragmente Buchgesellschaft. der Vorsokratiker. Griechisch und deutsch. Erster Fowler, Robert L. 2011: Mythos and logos. In: The Journal Band. 13. Auflage, unveränderter Nachdruck der 6. of Hellenic Studies 131: 45–66. Auflage. Zürich, Weidmann. Frede, Dorothea 2020: Aristoteles, Nikomachische Diogenes Laertius 2008: Leben und Meinungen berühm- Ethik. Übersetzt, eingeleitet und kommentiert. ter Philosophen. In der Übersetzung von Otto Apelt Zweiter Halbband: Kommentar. Berlin, de Gruyter. unter Mitarbeit von Hans Günter Zekl neu heraus- Frisk, Hjalmar 2006: Griechisches etymologisches gegeben sowie mit Einleitung und Anmerkungen Wörterbuch. Band II: Κρ–Ω. Vierte, unveränderte versehen von Klaus Reich. 2 Bände. Hamburg, Meiner. Auflage. Heidelberg, Winter. Dörrie, Heinrich/Wegenast, Klaus 1979: Logos. In: Ziegler, Futter, Dylan B. 2018: Spiritual pregnancy in Plato’s Konrat/Sontheimer, Walther (eds): Der Kleine Pauly. Theaetetus. In: Apeiron 51 (4): 483–514. Lexikon der Antike. Auf der Grundlage von Pauly’s Genesis = Biblia Hebraica Stuttgartensia 1997: Editio Realencyclopädie der classischen Altertumswissen- funditus renovata. Ediderunt Karl Elliger, Wilhelm Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 10
Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie Alfred Dunshirn | Logos, I. Antiquity | 2021 | doi: 10.11588/oepn.2021.2.83012 Rudolph. Editio quinta emendata opera Adrian Horoi = Plato 1907: Opera. Recognovit brevique ad- Schenker. Stuttgart, Deutsche Bibelgesellschaft. notatione critica instruxit Ioannes Burnet. Tomus V. Gettier, Edmund L. 1963: Is justified true belief knowl- Oxford, Clarendon Press. edge? In: Analysis 23 (6): 121–123. Hünermann, Peter 2009: Logos. III. Systematisch-theo- Gianvittorio, Laura 2010: Il discorso di Eraclito. Un logisch. In: Kasper, Walter (ed.): Lexikon für Theologie modello semantico e cosmologico nel passaggio und Kirche. Sechster Band: Kirchengeschichte bis dall’oralità alla scrittura. Hildesheim, Olms. Maximianus. Sonderausgabe (Durchgesehene Aus- Gill, Mary Louise 2003: Why does Theaetetus’ final gabe der 3. Auflage 1993–2001): 1029–1031. definition of knowledge fail? In: Detel, Wolfgang/ Janke, Wolfgang 2007: Plato. Antike Theologien des Becker, Alexander/Scholz, Peter (eds): Ideal and Cul- Staunens. Würzburg, Königshausen & Neumann. ture of Knowledge in Plato. Akten der 4. Tagung der John = Nestle/Aland 2013: Novum Testamentum Graece. Karl-und-Gertrud-Abel-Stiftung vom 1.–3. September Begründet von Eberhard und Erwin Nestle. Heraus- 2000 in Frankfurt. Stuttgart, Steiner: 159–173. gegeben von Barbara und Kurt Aland. 28., revidierte Gögler, Rolf 1963: Zur Theologie des biblischen Wortes Auflage, 2., korrigierter Druck. Herausgegeben vom bei Origenes. Düsseldorf, Patmos. Institut für Neutestamentliche Textforschung Müns- Gordon, Richard L./Ierodiakonou, Katerina 1999: Logos. ter/Westfalen unter der Leitung von Holger Strut- In: Cancik, Hubert/Schneider, Helmuth (eds): Der neue wolf. Stuttgart, Deutsche Bibelgesellschaft. Pauly. Enzyklopädie der Antike. Band 7: Lef–Men. Johansen, Thomas K. 2017: Aristotle on the logos of the Stuttgart, Metzler: 401–408. craftsman. In: Phronesis 62: 97–135. Graeser, Andreas 1991: Platons Auffassung von Wissen Johnstone, Mark A. 2014: On ‘logos’ in Heraclitus. In: und Meinung in Politeia V. In: Philosophisches Jahr- Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 47: 1–29. buch 98: 365–388. Jungen, Oliver/Lohnstein, Horst 2007: Geschichte der Guthrie, William K. C. 1985: A History of Greek Philosophy. Grammatiktheorie. Von Dionysios Thrax bis Noam Volume I: The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythago- Chomsky. München, Fink. reans. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Justin, Apologia prima pro Christianis = St. Justin Martyr Hadas-Lebel, Mireille 2012: Philo of Alexandria. A 1997: The First and Second Apologies. Translated and Thinker in the Jewish Diaspora. Translated by Robyn Edited by Leslie W. Barnard. New York, Paulist Press. Fréchet. Leiden, Brill. Kahn, Charles H. 1969: Stoic logic and Stoic LOGOS. In: Halfwassen, Jens 2004: Plotin und der Neuplatonismus. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 51: 158–172. München, Beck. Kamesar, Adam 2004: The logos endiathetos and the Heidegger, Martin 1992: Platon: Sophistes. Herausgege- logos prophorikos in allegorical interpretation. Philo ben von Ingeborg Schüßler. Frankfurt/M., Klostermann. and the D-Scholia to the Iliad. In: Greek, Roman, and Heidegger, Martin 2000: Logos (Heraklit, Fragment 50). Byzantine Studies 44 (2): 163–181. In: Heidegger, Martin: Vorträge und Aufsätze. Her- Karfik, Filip 2004: Die Beseelung des Kosmos. Untersu- ausgegeben von Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann. chungen zur Kosmologie, Seelenlehre und Theologie Frankfurt/M., Klostermann: 211–234. in Platons Phaidon und Timaios. München, Saur. Hetzel, Andreas 2011: Die Wirksamkeit der Rede. Zur Karfik, Filip 2020: Disorderly motion and the world soul Aktualität klassischer Rhetorik für die moderne in the Timaeus. In: Helmig, Christoph (ed.): World Sprachphilosophie. Bielefeld, transcript. Soul – Anima Mundi. On the Origins and Fortunes of Höffe, Otfried 2006: Aristoteles. 3., überarbeitete Auf- a Fundamental Idea. Berlin, de Gruyter: 63–76. lage. München, Beck. Kelber, Wilhelm 1986: Die Logoslehre. Von Heraklit bis Homer: Ilias = Homer 1996: Homeri Ilias. Recognovit Origenes. Frankfurt/M., Fischer. Helmut van Thiel. Hildesheim, Olms. König, Robert 2019: Logik + Mystik. 2 Bände. Norderstedt, Horn, Christoph 2005: logos/Wortkombination, Rede, Books on Demand. Sprache, Vernunft. In: Höffe, Otfried (ed.): Aristoteles- König, Robert 2020: Syllogistik und Dialektik bei Aristo- Lexikon. Stuttgart, Kröner: 329–333. teles und Platon. In: Rendl, Lois Marie/König, Robert Online Encyclopedia Philosophy of Nature | Online Lexikon Naturphilosophie 11
You can also read