On the nouniness of V2-clauses under preference predicates
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
On the nouniness of V2-clauses under preference predicates Frank Sode – Goethe University Frankfurt DGfS Arbeitgruppe 7 – February 26, 2021 1 / 40
Topic of the talk The topic of this talk are embedded V2-clauses in construction with predicates expressing a desire or preference as illustrated in (1). (1) a. Es wäre gut, ich wäre schon zu Hause. It be.SUBJ good I be.SUBJ already at home ‘It would be good if I was already at home.’ b. Ich wäre froh, ich wäre schon zu Hause. I be.SUBJ happy I be.SUBJ already at home ‘I would be happy if I was already at home.’ c. Ich { wollte / wünschte }, ich wäre schon zu Hause. I { want.SUBJ / wish } I be.SUBJ already at home ‘I wish I was already at home.’ 2 / 40
Topic of the talk I will pursue mainly two claims: • Empirical claim: These V2-clauses are a special kind of what Williams (1974) and Pesetsky (1991) call complement fulfilling conditionals. • Theoretical claim: These V2-clauses are the counterfactual counterpart of the nouny factive complements of the same predicates. 3 / 40
What are “complement fulfilling cond’s”? Williams (1974) was the first to notice that there is something special about sentences like (2-a). At the surface, (2-a) looks like a regular conditional; take for example (2-b). (2) a. Mary would be glad if she won the lottery. b. Mary would be rich if she won the lottery. The reasons for Williams to doubt that (2-a) is a regular conditional is that predicates like glad are factive predicates that require a complement. They cannot be used predicatively or attributively like happy. (3) a. I am { happy / *glad }. b. I am a { happy / *glad } person. (4) Mary is glad that she won the lottery. ; Mary won the lottery. 4 / 40
Williams on “complement fulfilling cond’s”? Intuitively, the idea is that glad introduces an additional argument slot that is left open. (5) a. [ Mary would be glad ][ if she won the lottery ] b. [ Mary would be rich ][ if she won the lottery ] Williams assumption is that this argument slot is somehow filled by a proposition made salient in the if-clause. The resulting reading according to Williams assumptions is: (6) [ Mary would be glad that she won the lottery ][ if she won the lottery ] 5 / 40
Williams’ idea (7) [ Mary would be glad that she won the lottery ][ if she won the lottery ] • On Williams’ analysis the if -clause plays a double role: It not only specifies the conditions under which “gladness” holds. • It also fulfills the complement requirement of glad and thus specifies the subject matter (Pesetsky), or what the “gladness” is all about. • In that sense, the conditional is complement fulfilling (Pesetsky). • I follow Pesetsky in calling the corresponding conditionals “complement fulfilling conditionals” = CFCs. 6 / 40
Two classes of modal evaluatives Williams points that CFCs distinguish two classes of modal evaluatives. Class 1 Class 2 unlikely, convinced, . . . good, glad, happy, . . . that-clauses non-factive factive allow CFCs * X (8) a. *It would be unlikely if Bob left. (Williams, 1974, p. 158) b. *I would be convinced if Bob left. (Williams, 1974, p. 158) (9) a. It would be good if Bob left. b. I would be happy if Bob left. 7 / 40
Why Williams’ analysis is beautiful • Williams analysis explains the outer appearance of a conditional (It is a conditional!) • It allows to keep the standard analysis of glad as an (emotive) factive predicate that takes a proposition as its argument and presupposes its truth in the world of evaluation. • It explains the vanishing of factivity as a textbook case of filtering in conditionals. • The only thing needed is a story for the copying of the proposition expressed in the conditional clause. • The details are provided by Pesetsky (1991)’s If Copying Rule. 8 / 40
Pesetsky’s If Copying Rule Following Williams (1974), Pesetsky assumes that the sentence in (10-a) has an interpretation in the sense of (10-b). (10) a. John would like it if Mary knew French. → [If Copying Rule] b. John would like it that Mary knows French if Mary knew French. 9 / 40
Pesetsky’s If Copying Rule This interpretation comes about by applying the following mechanism: (11) If Copying Rule Pesetsky (1991) 1. Take a clause k of the form [IF IP] where k modifies a sentence Σ. 2. Copy k as k’ substituting that for IF, making appropriate changes in mood so as to replace irrealis with realis mood marking. 3. Place k’ in an argument position of Σ. Leave k as an adjunct modifer. (It gets interpreted as a restrictive clause, with Σ the nuclear scope.) 4. k’ is factive. (12) a. [Σ John would like it ][ IF [IP Mary knew French ]] b. k’ = [ that [IP Mary knows French ]] c. [Σ John would like it ][ IF [IP Mary knew French ]] z }| { [ that [IP Mary knows French ]] 10 / 40
Two ways to arrive at Williams’ reading As Pesetsky points out: There are now two ways that we can arrive at an interpretation in the sense of Williams: Way 1: with a fronted if-clause via a referential pronoun: (unexciting) (13) If Mary knew French, John would like iti . for g (i ) = Jthat Mary knows FrenchK This pattern can be found with a wide range of factive predicates: see for example Schueler (2013); Hinterwimmer (2014); Schwabe (2016). Way 2: via the IC Rule (restricted to a certain class of factive predicates) (14) John would like it if Mary knew French. [Σ John would like it ][ IF [IP Mary knew French ]] z }| { [ that [IP Mary knows French ]] Pesetsky only calls the second kind of conditionals CFCs. 11 / 40
Evidence for two ways / Pesetsky’s IC Rule Pesetsky argues that we actually need something like the If Copying Rule to account for contrasts as the following: While the referential construction allows for the proposition to be picked up by referential that, (15-a), CFCs exlude referential that, (15-b). (15) a. If unicorns existedi , I would love thati . (Pesetsky, 1991, p. 74) b. *I would love thati if unicorns existedi . (Pesetsky, 1991, p. 74) His explanation: The If Copying Rule doesn’t allow to overwrite truly referential pronouns like that. (Pesetsky disccusses more differences.) 12 / 40
Extension to desire reports The If Copying Rule not only plays a role in Pesetsky’s account of CFCs. It also plays a crucial role in Pesetsky’s analysis of desire reports. (16) Pesetsky (1991)’s Post-LF analysis of want (+ ∅for -complement) John wants [ ∅for Mary to know French ] → John would like [ ∅for Mary to know French ] → [If Copying Rule] John would like (it) that Mary knows French, IF Mary knew French. For Pesetsky, ∅for -clauses as the complements of desire verbs like want are hidden CFCs that combine with a hidden factive preference predicate. 13 / 40
Complement fulfilling conditionals “Williams-Pesetsky-Class”: the class of predicates that license CFCs. (17) The Williams-Pesetsky-Class of predicates a. Prioriety-oriented modal evaluatives: good, glad, happy, . . . b. Desire verbs: want, wish, like, love, . . . 14 / 40
Embedded V2 in German 15 / 40
Embedded V2-complements Two basic assumptions in the literature 1 Only predicates with a non-negative “assertive” meaning license V2-complements. (18) a. Die Maria { glaubt / sagt }, man hört ihr zu. the Maria { believes / says } one listens her to ‘Maria { believes / says } that people listen to her.’ b. *Die Maria { fordert / beweifelt }, man hört ihr zu. the Maria { demands / doubts } one listens her to ‘Maria { demands / doubts } that people listen to her.’ 2 Embedded V2-clauses are root phenomena. Helbig & Kempter (1974); Reis (1997); Gärtner (2002); Truckenbrodt (2006) ... 16 / 40
Puzzling cases A certain class of non-assertive predicates, often characterized as “preference predicates” or “volitional predicates”, seem to license what looks like V2-complements. (19) a. Es wäre gut, ich wäre schon zu Hause. It be.SUBJ good I be.SUBJ already at home ‘It would be good if I was already at home.’ b. Ich wäre froh, ich wäre schon zu Hause. I be.SUBJ happy I be.SUBJ already at home ‘I would be happy if I was already at home.’ c. Ich { wollte / wünschte }, ich wäre schon zu Hause. I { want.SUBJ / wish } I be.SUBJ already at home ‘I wish I was already at home.’ Helbig & Kempter (1974); Reis (1997); Frank (1998); Meinunger (2007) 17 / 40
Puzzling cases A first crucial observation is that the corresponding V2-clauses are licensed only in subjunctive mood but not in indicative mood.* (20) a. *Es ist gut, ich bin schon zu Hause. It be.IND good I be.IND already at home b. *Ich bin froh, ich bin schon zu Hause. I be.IND happy I be.IND already at home c. *Ich will, ich bin schon zu Hause. I want I be.IND already at home * for more discussion and exceptions see: Frank (1998); Meinunger (2007) 18 / 40
The connection to CFCs 19 / 40
The connection to CFCs First, all puzzling cases seem to belong in the Williams-Pesetsky-Class: (21) The Williams-Pesetsky-Class of predicates a. Prioriety-oriented modal evaluatives: good, glad, happy, . . . b. Desire verbs: want, wish, like, love, . . . 20 / 40
The connection to CFCs Second, these embedded V2-clauses are more naturally paraphrased with wenn (‘if’)-clauses in subjunctive mood than with dass (‘that’)-clauses, cf. Frank (1998); Meinunger (2007). (22) Es wäre gut, ich wäre schon zu Hause. It be.SUBJ good I be.SUBJ already at home ‘It would be good if I was already at home.’ can be paraphrased as (23) Es wäre gut, { wenn / ??/*dass } ich schon zu Hause It be.SUBJ good { if / that }I already at home wäre. be.SUBJ ‘It would be good if I was already at home.’ 21 / 40
The connection to CFCs “CondV2-clauses”: V2-clauses as “complements” of the predicates in the Williams- Pesetsky-Class. CondV2-clauses are a special kind of complement fulfilling conditionals. (Similar to Pesetsky’s ∅for -complements.) On the following slides, I present evidence in favour of this claim. 22 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 1: Although CondV2-clauses can be paraphrased by wenn (‘if’)-clauses; they don’t allow to be interpreted as “true” conditionals. While the V2-clause in (24) (that can be paraphrase with a conditional clause) is fine with a predicate from the Williams-Pesetsky-Class . . . (24) Der Peter wäre froh, der Hans würde seine Schulden the Peter be.SUBJ happy the Hans will.SUBJ his debts bei ihm begleichen. with him settle ‘Peter would be happy if Hans paid back his debts.’ V2 23 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 1: . . . a “true” conditional interpretation is not possible. (25) *Der Peter wäre reich, der Hans würde seine Schulden the Peter be.SUBJ rich the Hans will.SUBJ his debts bei ihm begleichen. with him settle intended: ‘Peter would be rich if Hans paid back his debts.’ V2 This is different from V1-clauses that do allow “true” conditional interpretations; compare (26). (26) Der Peter wäre reich, würde der Hans seine Schulden the Peter be.SUBJ rich will.SUBJ the Hans his debts bei ihm begleichen. with him settle ‘Peter would be rich if Hans paid back his debts.’ V1 24 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 2: CondV2-clauses don’t allow referential pronouns. (more discussion ⇒ Appendix) (27) a. Ich fände es gut, es würde mal wieder regnen. I find.SUBJ it good it will.SUBJ once again rain ‘I would like it if it finally rained again.’ b. *Ich fände das gut, es würde mal wieder regnen. I find.SUBJ that good it will.SUBJ once again rain intended: ‘I would like it if it finally rained again.’ 25 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 3: CondV2-clauses only allow desire object interpretations. This is similar to an observation made by Grosz (2012) for English CFCs. (28) a. It’s not the case that I want John to be here, but if he were here, it would be nice that he was here. b. #It’s not the case that I want John to be here, but it would be nice if he was here. cf. Grosz (2012) (29) Ich will zwar nicht, dass der Hans kommt, aber . . . ‘I don’t want Hans to come but . . . ’ a. #es wäre schön, er wäre hier. it be.SUBJ nice he be.SUBJ here #‘it would be nice if he were here.’ V2 b. es wäre schön, wäre er hier. it be.SUBJ nice be.SUBJ he here ‘. . . if he were here, it would be nice.’ V1 26 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 3: They only allow desire object interpretations. The interpretation of wünschte is in a conceptual conflict with the modal sollte (‘should’) on a deontic interpretation. (30) Ich wünschte, der Hans { würde / #sollte } seine Schulden I wish.SUBJ the Hans { will.SUBJ / should } his debts bei mir begleichen. with me settle ‘I wish Hans paid back the money he owes me.’ 27 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 3: They only allow desire object interpretations. The use of sollte (‘should’) in the V2-clause in (31-a) has the same feeling to it. Sollte in a V1-clause is possible; but the interpretation of sollte flips to the deliberative interpretation of sollte found in conditionals. (31) a. #Ich wäre froh, der Hans sollte seine Schulden bei I be.SUBJ happy the Hans should his debts with mir begleichen. me settle V2 b. Ich wäre froh, sollte der Hans seine Schulden bei mir I be.SUBJ happy should the Hans his debts with me begleichen. settle ‘If Hans should pay back the money he owes me, I would be happy.’ V1 28 / 40
Summary • The V2-clauses under discussion only show up in the Williams-Pesetsky-Class that license CFCs. • They can be paraphrased by wenn (‘if’)-clauses; not by dass (‘that’)-clauses. • They don’t allow to be picked up by referential pronouns. • They only allow for desire object interpretations similar to CFCs in English (cf. Grosz (2012)). CondV2-clauses are a special kind of complement fulfilling conditionals. 29 / 40
Nouniness? 30 / 40
What’s the nouniness? Desire reports are often analysed along the lines of Heim (1992) assuming a structure as follows: (32) Mary is gladFACTIVE [CP that ϕ ]st standard assumption We can arrive at the same truth conditions with the following structure that assumes a different distribution of the elements provided by Heim’s analysis at the syntax-semantics interface; Sode (2020): s(st )t (33) [ Mary is gladNEUTRAL PROi ][ @FACTIVE [CP that ϕ ]st ]i PRO fills an argument slot of the semantic type s(st )t. 31 / 40
What’s the nouniness? s(st )t (34) [ Mary is gladNEUTRAL PROi ][ @FACTIVE [CP that ϕ ]st ]i (34) ≈ ‘Mary desires what is the case (according to her beliefs) since that ϕ’ This proposal is (a) closer in spirit to what Heim literally (=by way of her paraphrases) proposes, which can be summarized by the following slogan: “There is a hidden ‘because’-clause in every factive desire report.” (‘because’-clause ≈ factive conditional) (b) closer in spirit to ideas found in the syntactic literature on factive complements (going back at least to Kiparsky & Kiparsky (1970)): The assumption is that factive complements are (a) nouny (which shows up in their semantic type: hs, hhs, t i, t ii ≈ type of intensional objects); (b) involve a hidden factive operator (here: more determiner than noun). 32 / 40
Advantages of the analysis The semantic type of glad is now such that it can directly combine with an if -clause in intension (or more precisely: an if -restricted operator). For the counterfactual case, we can simply assume that be glad combines with would if ϕ as its semantic argument. s(st )t (35) a. [ Mary is gladNEUTRAL PROi ][ @FACTIVE [CP that ϕ ]st ]i s(st )t b. [ Mary be gladNEUTRAL PROi ][ would [CP if ϕ ]st ]i (35-b) ≈ ‘Mary desires what would be the case (according to her beliefs) if ϕ’ would is the counterfactual counterpart of the factive operator @. (I assume this analysis can be extended to other predicates in the Williams-Pesetsky-Class.) For more arguments for this analysis see Sode (2020). Additional comments: ⇒ appendix. 33 / 40
Analysis In analogy, we can think of CondV2-clauses as restricting a hidden conditional operator WOULD (that I assume to be also present in regular counterfactual conditionals of German). s(st )t (36) a. [ ich PROi froh wäre ][ WOULD [CP er wäre hier ]st ]i s(st )t b. [ esPROi gut wäre ][ WOULD [CP er wäre hier ]st ]i CondV2 Analysis: CondV2-clauses are a special kind of IF-clause. They can only restrict a conditional operator that fills an argument slot of a pred- icate in the Williams-Pesetsky-Class. (Similar to Pesetsky’s ∅for -complements.) 34 / 40
Conclusion • Empirically: CondV2-clauses have the distribution and interpretation of complement fulfilling conditionals. • Analysis: CondV2-clauses are semantically interpreted as IF-clauses. Their use is restricted: They can only restrict operators in a thematic argument position of predicates in the Williams-Pesetsky-Class. • These arguments share the nouniness of the corresponding factive clauses. • Confirms the suspicion expressed in Frank (1998); Meinunger (2007) that V2-clauses under preference predicates are of a different kind than V2-complements under assertive predicates. • That is: Not all embedded V2-clauses are root phenomena. 35 / 40
Literature I Frank, Nicola. 1998. Präferenzprädikate und abhängige Verbzweitsätze. Magisterarbeit Universität Tübingen. Arbeitspapiere des SFB 340. Bericht Nr. 128. Grosz, Patrick Georg. 2012. On the grammar of optative constructions. Amsterdam: Benjamins. Heim, Irene. 1992. Presupposition Projection and the Semantics of Attitude Verbs. Journal of Semantics 9.3. 183–221. Helbig, G. & F. Kempter. 1974. Die uneingeleiteten Nebensätze im Deutschen und ihre Vermittlung im Fremdsprachenunterricht. DAF 11. 75–86. Hinterwimmer, Stefan. 2014. If vs. when, wenn vs. als: Microvariation in the Semantics of Conditional and Temporal Complementizers in English and German. Kaufmann, Magda. 2017. Japanese modals and other evaluations. MIT, Seminar “The Linguistics of Desire”, November 29. 36 / 40
Literature II Kiparsky, Paul & Carol Kiparsky. 1970. Fact. In M. Bierwisch & K.E. Heidolph (eds.), Progress in linguistics, 143–173. Mouton. Longenbaugh, Nicholas. 2019. On expletives and the agreement-movement correlation: Department of Linguistics and Philosophy. MIT dissertation. Meinunger, André. 2007. In the mood of desire and hope. In Tense, Mood and Aspect, 155–176. Amsterdam, New York: Rodopi. Pesetsky, D. 1991. Zero syntax. Vol. 2: Infinitives. Manuscript. Reis, Marga. 1997. Zum syntaktischen Status unselbständiger Verbzweit-Sätze. In C. Dürscheid, K. H. Ramers & M. Schwarz (eds.), Sprache im Fokus, 121–144. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Schueler, David. 2013. Factivity and presuppositions. University of Minnesota, Twin Cities, LSA Annual Meeting 2013. Schwabe, Kerstin. 2016. Sentential proforms and argument conditionals 211–240. John Benjamins Publishing Company. Williams, Edwin Samuel. 1974. Rule ordering in syntax. Cambrigde, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology dissertation. 37 / 40
CondV2-clauses are CFCs Evidence 2: CondV2-clauses don’t allow referential pronouns. (37) Denkst du, es wäre gut, die Klausur mitzuschreiben? ‘Do you think that it would be good to write the exam?’ a. Naja, das wäre gut, wenn wir was dafür getan Well it be.SUBJ good if we what for.that done hätten. have.SUBJ ‘Well, it would be good if we had studied for it.’ b. *Naja, das wäre gut, wir hätten was dafür getan. Well that be.SUBJ good we have.SUBJ what for.that done c. #Naja, es wäre gut, wir hätten was dafür getan. Well that be.SUBJ good we have.SUBJ what for.that done #‘Well, it would be good to have studied for it.’ in the sense of (37-a) 38 / 40
Advantages of the analysis There is no need for Pesetsky’s If Copying Rule anymore. The assumption of such a rule was only necessary given the assumption that the predicates in the Williams-Pesetsky-Class on a factive interpretation take arguments of a propositional type. The crucial difference in interpretation to the Williams-Pesetsky-Account of CFCs is that the conditional clause is only used to characterize the object of desire on this account (in agreement with Grosz (2012)’s observation) and not to characterize the counterfactual situations under which happiness will be achieved (as predicted by Williams’ paraphrase). This is a good result since it has recently been argued that Williams’ paraphrase doesn’t capture the right truth conditions: Grosz (2012); Kaufmann (2017); Longenbaugh (2019); Sode (2020). 39 / 40
Factive predicates (38) a. Ich wäre froh, wenn ich schon zu Hause wäre. b. Ich wäre froh, ich wäre schon zu Hause. (39) a. Ich wäre überrascht, wenn ich schon zu Hause wäre. b. *Ich wäre überrascht, ich wäre schon zu Hause. (40) a. Ich würde (es) wissen, wenn ich schon zu Hause wäre. b. *Ich würde (es) wissen, ich wäre schon zu Hause. (41) a. Ich würde (es) bedauern, wenn ich schon zu Hause wäre. b. *Ich würde (es) bedauern, ich wäre schon zu Hause. 40 / 40
You can also read