Is a One Welfare Approach the Key to Addressing Unintended Harms and Maximising Benefits Associated with Animal Shelters?
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 brill.com/jaae Is a One Welfare Approach the Key to Addressing Unintended Harms and Maximising Benefits Associated with Animal Shelters? Anne Fawcett School of Veterinary Science, University of Sydney, Australia anne.fawcett@sydney.edu.au Abstract Animal shelters, pounds and rescue organisations have evolved over time. Today they serve three purposes: to reduce animal welfare harms, to reduce harms to the com- munity associated with free-roaming, stray or unwanted companion animals, and to reduce their associated environmental harms. This discussion explores the evolu- tion of animal shelters, and argues that they are justified on utilitarian grounds. It explores unintended harms of shelters on animal welfare, including humane killing for the purposes of population control and shelter population management, as well as risks associated with confinement including behavioural deterioration and infec- tious diseases. It also explores harms to non-human animals, including moral distress and compassion fatigue. Finally, it explores potential environmental harms of shelters. The One Welfare concept, utilised in the World Animal Health Organisation (OIE) Global Animal Welfare Strategy, acknowledges the interplay between animal welfare, human well-being and environmental sustainability. It is argued that the One Welfare framework is critical in minimising harms and maximising benefits associated with animal shelters. Keywords One Welfare – animal shelter – euthanasia – death as a harm – compassion fatigue – moral distress – companion animal overpopulation © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2019 | doi:10.1163/25889567-12340010 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
178 Fawcett … There is no simple solution to the complex problem of animal overpopu- lation and shelters remain an interim solution for the foreseeable future. Turner et al., 2012 ∵ 1 Introduction Shelters, pounds and animal rescue organisations house lost, stray, and unwanted companion animals, as well as those seized from cruelty cases such as hoarding situations and puppy farms. By housing animals that may otherwise free-roam they reduce the animal welfare, public health and safety and environmental problems caused by free-roaming animals (Turner et al., 2012). However, as discussed in this paper, sheltering animals incurs harms (or ‘costs’)—to animal welfare, human well-being, and the environment. In May 2017, the World Organisation for Animal Health (OIE) released its global animal welfare strategy, based on the “One Welfare” concept in which members are encouraged to work towards animal welfare, human well-being (including social and economic development) and environmental sustainabil- ity concurrently (OIE, 2017a). There are currently no reports of the application of the One Welfare concept to animal shelters. This paper will briefly discuss the evolution of animal shelters to date, followed by a discussion of the ethical justification for animal shelters. After that, I will explore the unintended harms of shelters in relation to animals, humans and the environment, and finally, I will discuss why a One Welfare approach is critical in reducing unintended harms, and maximising benefits, of animal shelters. 2 A Word on Terminology In the veterinary context, the term “euthanasia” is often used to refer to a death brought about humanely, regardless of the reasons for effecting that humane death. However, it is important, for reasons outlined by this author Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 179 in a previous discussion (Fawcett, 2013), to distinguish euthanasia (killing an animal in its own interests) from killing an animal which is not in its interests (for example, a young healthy animal killed to reduce crowding). In 2004 the Asilomar Accords were developed to standardise definitions used by shelters, for example what is meant by “healthy”, “treatable”, “manageable”, “unhealthy”, “untreatable” (Asilomar Accords, 2004). What constitutes “treatable” varies be- tween shelters and may be determined by many non-biological factors includ- ing funding, access to resources, and staff. For the purposes of this discussion, the term euthanasia will be used to refer to the humane killing of an unhealthy, untreatable animal with a view to end suffering (“a life not worth living”), while “killing” will be used to refer to deaths (humane or otherwise) of healthy, treatable animals brought about for other reasons, such as population control. Such killing may be morally justifiable, but in the author’s view does not meet the criteria for use of the term “euthanasia”. 3 The Evolution of Animal Shelters While the evolution of animal shelters is highly context specific, there has been a general trend from a model of animal control to one of care. The aim of pounds was once to reduce the unwanted animal population through killing excess animals, whereas the aim of modern day shelters is to ensure that as many animals as possible are placed in, or returned to, their homes. This evolution is discussed by Miller & Zawistowski (2012), who describe the development of US animal shelters from livestock pounds in towns and villages (Miller & Zawistowski, 2012). The poundmaster would round up “stray” animals—normally farm or work animals like pigs, chickens, goats, cattle or horses—then impound them. Owners of impounded animals were required to pay a fee to have the animal released. The poundmaster could keep the remain- ing animals for his personal use, or sell them. The poundmaster’s income was derived from impoundment fees, livestock sales, and produce which may be sold or used to feed his own family. Stray dogs were more problematic as these were less likely to be sold, and would not be used for food. The poundmaster could impound dogs, but the unclaimed majority were eventually killed. As people moved from villages to towns and cities, fewer owned livestock, but stray dogs flourished on scraps and rubbish concentrated in urban environ- ments. The impound became known as the dog pound. Because their salaries relied heavily on impounding fees, dog catchers commonly kidnapped owned dogs and demanded fees from the owners, while unowned dogs continued to Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
180 Fawcett stray and reproduce. Some impounded dogs were sold for research, having perhaps been deliberately procured by the pound for this purpose (National Research Council [US], 2009). One of the big issues faced by pounds was how to dispose of unwanted dogs. In the 1870s, the pound in New York City resorted to drowning dogs by lowering them into the East River in a large iron cage as the public watched (Miller & Zawistowski, 2012; Pierce, 2016a). Until this time, facilities that we now know as animal shelters were im- poundment facilities designed exclusively to benefit humans—the wider com- munity, the poundmaster or dogcatcher, the municipal council—without any consideration for animal welfare. Over time the concept of humane animal shelters developed. The noun shelter is defined as “a place giving temporary protection from bad weath- er or danger” while the verb means “to protect or shield from something harmful, especially bad weather” (English Oxford Living Dictionaries, 2017). Shelter is one of the Five Freedoms and Provisions for Animal Welfare, which requires provision of an appropriate environment and comfortable resting area. According to David Mellor, a shelter should not just protect animals from negative welfare states, but promote positive welfare states (Mellor, 2016). Humane animal shelters were conceived as places where dogs (and later cats) could receive food, water, shelter, veterinary care, and perhaps be adopt- ed into a new home. Animals without homes would be “better off” in shelters. Those that could not be rehomed were “humanely” killed. Over the 20th Century, the way humans interacted with companion animals changed dramatically. Companion animals, once permitted to stray, were in- creasingly confined to the owner’s property, which soon became a legislated requirement. They began to be treated as family members (Serpell, 1996; Amiot et al., 2016). In the 1980s, shelters came under increasing criticism for relying on killing as a means of addressing animal overpopulation. In what was to become a highly influential essay, Edward Duvin claimed that the prevailing shelter value system was “a convoluted system that places a higher operational priority on ‘painless’ execution than preventative education” (Duvin, 1989). He added that “shelters will continue to be nothing more than processing plants until they begin the transition from sanitation dumps for the public’s unwanted ‘baggage’ to vital community education centres”. Duvin argued that shelters had failed in their moral obligation to ensure decisions around life and death were based on validated outcome measures, that busy shelter staff were too “mired in daily operational and fundraising Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 181 activities” to tackle companion animal overpopulation at the source, uncriti- cally accepting that killing is “an acceptable and merciful act” (Duvin, 1989). Shelters, he argued, were not the safe havens people the public believed they should be, and in many cases caused harm. As such, animals were better off left to their own devices than housed in the worst shelters. “Whether picked up on the street or surrendered at the shelter, the vast majority of these animals experience the kind of psychological trauma and terror that we find so abhorrent for caged laboratory animals but tolerate in our own facilities. Some are exposed to various forms of physical mishandling and abuse, and all suffer from the anguishing ordeal of being processed and warehoused in a foreign and frightening environment. Euthanasia might be a relatively painless end to this journey of terror, but each death represents an abject failure—not an act of mercy” (Duvin, 1989). A true shelter, according to Duvin, should be “a place where life is affirmed, both in teaching and practice, not a building permeated with the odour of death”. Duvin’s paper was published 30 years ago. Shelters, pounds and rescue or- ganisations have continued to evolve since then. Significantly, the “no-kill” movement, of which Duvin is sometimes referred to as the father (Miller & Zawistowski, 2012), has been influential in changing policies around killing and, to some extent, euthanasia, in animal welfare organisations. Our relationships with companion animals evolved further still, with legisla- tion reflecting this. For example, the UK Animal Welfare Act 2006, enshrines the duty of persons responsible for an animal to ensure an animal’s welfare. Thus “a person commits an offence if he does not take such steps as are reasonable in all circumstances to ensure that the needs of the animal for which he is responsible are met to the extent required by good practice” (UK Animal Welfare Act 2006 at http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2006/45/section/9/2007-03-23). In some contexts, microchipping and visual identification (collar and tag) are mandated, which not only increases return of lost animals to owners (Dingman et al., 2014), but also ensures that an owner who is accountable for an animal’s welfare can be traced, and may aid in enforcement of legislation (Companion Animals Act [NSW], 2017). In many contexts, shelters have evolved into adoption centres, with an emphasis on placing the right animal in the right home to reduce the risk of re-surrender. Many shelters now collect data to analyse outcomes, including post-adoption interviews. More shelters provide enriched housing, promote positive interactions between staff, volunteers and animals, and aim to meet the welfare needs of animals housed. More staff are equipped with at least basic principles of animal behaviour to ensure that welfare needs of animals are better met in shelters, and many shelters formally evaluate the behaviour Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
182 Fawcett Table 1 Providers of low or no-cost educational resources for shelters and animal welfare organisations Organisation Website/resource Humane Society of the United States https://www.animalsheltering.org/ (HSUS) American Society for the Prevention of https://www.aspcapro.org/ Cruelty to Animals (ASPCA) Maddie’s Fund http://www.maddiesfund.org/index.htm University of Florida (in association with http://sheltermedicine.vetmed.ufl.edu/ Maddie’s Fund) The Royal Society for the Prevention of https://www.rspca.org.au/ Cruelty to Animals (RSPCA) Australia Getting 2 Zero http://www.g2z.org.au/ Association of Shelter Veterinarians http://www.sheltervet.org/ International Association of Animal https://iaabc.org/shelter Behaviour Consultants (IAABC) Shelter Division International Cat Care https://icatcare.org/ Cat Protection Society of NSW http://catcare.org.au/vet-professional -education-package/ of animals so they can be placed in suitable homes (Miller & Zawistowski, 2012). There are a huge number of low-cost or no-cost educational resources available to shelters through organisations outlined in Table 1. However, Duvin’s criticisms remain relevant as they highlight an inherent conflict between the stated purpose of shelters—to address animal overpopu- lation humanely—with the operational consequences: in the worst cases, un- wittingly perpetuating the problem and causing suffering, by hoarding animals in shelters, exposing them to overpopulation, poor hygiene and poor welfare. 4 The Ethical Basis of Shelters Animals may be admitted to shelters because it is believed that they are “better off”, that is, suffering less, in a shelter than elsewhere—whether elsewhere is straying, in an incompatible home, or being the victims of neglect or cruelty. They may also be admitted to shelters because humans—as members of the Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 183 general community or as pet owners—may be “better off” without the animal. For example, one may argue that a family with an incompatible pet, or one which they find themselves no longer in the circumstances to keep, may be suf- fering. This suffering can be relieved by surrendering the animal to the shelter. As a second example, consider an emaciated, parasite-ridden stray dog that follows people, defecates in the street and tips garbage over. The dog may be “better off” in a shelter where it is not exposed to the elements, and where food and water (and potentially parasite control and veterinary care) are reli- ably available. Furthermore, the wider canine community may be “better off” as contained dogs are unable to spread diseases like parvovirus, distemper or rabies. The human community and environment may be “better off” avoiding unsanitary conditions caused by the dog, without being annoyed or frightened by the dog, without the threat of zoonoses like rabies being transmitted via bites from such dogs, and without the distress of being confronted with the sight of this creature. When compared with life on the street or in an unsuitable, the shelter is intended to be—at least—the lesser of two evils. Ideally, a shelter is a place where animals experience not only a minimum of negative welfare states, but positive welfare states (Mellor, 2012). This aligns with a utilitarian approach of minimizing pain or suffering, while maximizing wellbeing. Crudely, a utilitarian approach seeks the best outcome (benefits) for as many stakeholders as possible, while reducing poor outcomes (harms) for as many stakeholders as possible, or, as Jeremy Bentham said: “the greatest amount of good for the greatest number” (Driver, 2014). John Stuart Mill, also a utilitarian, added an important caveat, known as “the harm prin- ciple”, according to which in seeking the greatest good for the greatest number, one must do so without causing avoidable harm to others. According to Mill, “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any mem- ber of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others” (Mill, 1865). Bentham’s utilitarian ethos is reflected in the way shelter outcomes are evaluated. The measure of shelter success is live release rate (LRR), which expresses as a percentage of intake the number of animals leaving a shelter alive, due to reclaim by owners, re-homing or transfer to another agency that guarantees animal adoption (Weiss et al., 2013). Theoretically, the higher the LRR, the better the outcome. The killing of animals in shelters is justified as a means of reducing the “unwanted” animal population, and/or as a means of ending current or future suffering (terminating a life not worth living). While kill rates reduce LRR, such killing is justified as minimizing current or future suffering. Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
184 Fawcett A utilitarian framework balances benefits (LRR) against harms (number of animals killed). One common criticism of utilitarian or consequentialist ethical frameworks is that they rely on accurate prediction of outcomes—yet, as will be discussed later, there can be unintended, unpredictable negative outcomes. Another ethical justification for animal shelters is relational. Writing specif- ically about dogs, Kristien Hens argues that dogs have evolved to exist within the human cultural context, and as such they occupy a special position from which obligations flow. Our relationship with dogs—and by extension other companion animals—obliges us to provide for their care, even when we can- not provide such care directly ourselves: “There is a bond of mutual trust be- tween dog and human that should not be breached” (Hens, 2009). This requires the establishment of “proper shelters”, as well as education of the public about what it means to own a dog, promotion of adoption of shelter dogs, and employment of dog behaviourists to match the “right dog” with the “right person” (Hens, 2009). Shelters that do not provide optimal welfare then fail in their mission to provide “proper care” for dogs, and presumably cats, that Hens argues we are obliged to. Shelters must be managed carefully to ensure they are not complicit in poor welfare. Bioethicist Jessica Pierce argues that, in some ways, shelters are part of the problem they seek to address. According to Pierce, the “shelter industry” seeks to grow or remain sustainable in the long-term. Pierce is highlighting a potential conflict of interest. Just like the dog catcher relied on impoundment fees, so too modern shelters rely on a large throughput of animals, but chasing their own redundancy is not financially viable. “Shelters rely on having a high census and adopting out as many animals as possible to maintain a flow of funding, which not only keeps animals fed but pays the meagre salaries of employees” (Pierce, 2016b). Pierce goes a step further and argues that shelters are complicit in ani- mal overpopulation, by looking after the surplus generated by one source of that overpopulation—the pet industry—thus maintaining a market for new “product”. She asks, if adopting an animal from a shelter compounds or rein- forces some welfare issues, whether we should opt out of the pet industry al- together. Pierce, a companion animal owner herself, stops short of concluding that we should not adopt companion animals from shelters. Rather, she is try- ing to draw our attention to welfare problems perpetuated by the companion animal industry. However, she raises the important prospect that shelters may be, at least in some ways, detrimental to animals in ways they aren’t intended to be. If this is the case, and if—in a utilitarian account—shelters do more harm than good, Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 185 it would be hard to defend them ethically. To address this concern, the shel- ters should aim to minimize harms or costs and maximise benefits to as many stakeholders as possible. The Three Rs of humane experimental technique (Russell & Burch, 1959), also a utilitarian framework, was designed to be applied to animal use in labo- ratory and teaching contexts, but could equally apply in a shelter setting. The Three Rs oblige us to replace the use of animals with non-animal models, re- duce the number of animals used and refine husbandry and experimental pro- cedures. In a shelter context, we may consider replacing killing as a form of population control, reducing the number of animals killed through practices that promote adoption and refinement of husbandry to promote adoption and prevent behavioural deterioration, as well as refinement of humane killing methods where these are used. To this end, shelters around the world employ different strategies to replace euthanasia as a means of population control—either by reducing shelter ad- missions or increasing animals adopted or reclaimed. Strategies include popu- lation control via surgical neutering of animals, permanent identification of animals via microchips so that lost animals can be reunited with owners faster, reducing re-surrenders by matching animals to households and vice versa, and reducing shelter-related harms to animals, including behavioural deterioration which may make them less adoptable. According to former RSPCA New South Wales Chief Veterinary Officer, Dr Magdoline Awad, “There are many shelters working towards reducing in- take and assisting pet owners as a means of reducing euthanasia and operating costs. Identifying the reasons for surrender and then designing programs that assist in keeping the pet at home are now the focus” (Awad, Small Animal Be- havioural Medicine Conference, Centre for Veterinary Education, 2017). But animals are not the only stakeholders. As discussed later in this paper, shelters have impacts on humans as well as the environment. A utilitarian ap- proach requires that we address the interests of all of these stakeholders to the greatest extent possible. 5 Animal Death as a Harm As discussed, historically, animals were killed inhumanely in shelters, for ex- ample by mass-drowning, electrocution, decompression chambers or carbon monoxide gas (Humane Society of the United States, 2013). In some parts of the world, other methods considered to be inhumane (OIE, 2017b) are still em- ployed including poisons such as strychnine and cyanide, drowning, hanging Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
186 Fawcett and use of curare-like drugs (World Society for the Protection of Animals, 2008; Tasker, 2009; Ortega-Pacheco & Jiménez-Coello, 2011). Gas chamber use for euthanasia was confirmed or suspected in four US states as late as July 2016 (Humane Society of the United States, 2016). Increasingly in shelters, animals are killed by lethal injection, with or with- out sedation, which is considered humane (World Society for the Protection of Animals, 2008; Newbury et al., 2010; Humane Society of the United States, 2013; Leary et al., 2013), yet this does require training and may not be accessible or legal in all countries. A discussion of the relative harm of methods of euthana- sia is beyond the scope of this paper, however it is uncontroversial that killing animals inhumanely is a harm best avoided. In addition to the potential to harm animals by the way that death is caused, the question remains whether bringing about the state of being dead is a harm. John Webster argued that being dead is “no problem at all” to an animal (Webster, 1994) because dead animals are not capable of experiencing negative (or positive) welfare states. Yet, as James Yeates argues, many people who work in shelters would consid- er the killing of a healthy animal to be, “at least in some cases, morally undesir- able” (Yeates, 2010). Furthermore, the argument that death is not a welfare issue could be used to argue that, since every life is likely to contain negative welfare states worth avoiding, every animal ought to be humanely killed, unless we could guarantee that that animal would not experience negative welfare states (Yeates, 2010). He argues that death is an ethical issue at least in part because it is a welfare issue, in that it excludes the possibility of experiencing positive welfare states. As he argues, “just as euthanasia excludes negative states; pre- venting a good life excludes positive states” (Yeates, 2010). Indeed, the benefit of shelters is in giving animals an opportunity to experience a life worth living. If we accept this argument, it follows that shelters that humanely kill healthy animals are still harming them by depriving those animals of future positive welfare states—lives worth living (Farm Animal Welfare Council, 2009). The numbers of animals involved are enormous (see Table 2). The Ameri- can Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals (ASPCA) estimated that 3.3 million dogs and 3.2 million cats are admitted to US animal shelters nation- ally every year, of which 1.5 million are euthanised or killed (670,000 dogs and 860,000 cats), 3.2 million are adopted (1.6 million each for dogs and cats) and 710,000 are reclaimed (620,000 dogs and 90,000 cats) (American Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals, 2017). In the UK, it was estimated that 131,070 cats and 129,743 dogs were admitted to animal welfare organisations during 2009 (Clark et al., 2012). Of these, 5,064 Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 187 Table 2 Outcomes of animals admitted to shelters, animal welfare organisations and/or municipal pounds in the US, UK and Australia Country Admitted Adopted Reclaimed Killed US animal shelters 3.3 million dogs 1.6 million dogs 620,000 dogs 670,000 dogs (American Society 3.2 million cats 1.6 million cats 90,000 cats 860,000 cats for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals, 2017) UK animal welfare 129,743 dogs N/A 12.5% dogs 7,142 dogs organisations 131,070 cats N/A 2.7% cats 5,064 cats (Clark et al., 2012) UK animal welfare 89,571 dogs 75% dogs N/A 10.4% dogs organisations 156,826 cats 77.1% cats N/A 13.2% cats (Stavisky et al., 2012) Australia shelters 211,655 dogs 66,443 dogs 101,037 dogs 43,900 dogs and municipal pounds (Chua et al., 2017) cats and 7142 dogs were reported to be euthanised, while 12.5% of dogs and 2.7% of cats were reclaimed. Another UK study estimated that 89,571 dogs and 156,826 cats were admitted to animal welfare organisations, with 75% of dogs and 77.1% of cats rehomed. It was estimated that 10.4% of dogs and 13.2% of cats were euthanised (Stavisky et al., 2012). A recent study utilizing data from Australian shelters and municipal pounds found that there were 211,655 dog admissions between 2012 and 2013. Of these, 101,037 (47.7%) were reclaimed, 66,443 (31.4%) were rehomed and 43,900 (20.7%) were euthanised or killed (Chua et al., 2017). The exact number of animals is impossible to determine, given the num- ber and variable nature of shelters, pounds and rescue organisations, different standards of record keeping, and the increasing transfer of animals between agencies (Simmons & Hoffman, 2016). Even harder is accurate documenta- tion of changing trends in the long term, as historically shelters have been poor collectors of data (Duvin, 1989). There are reports of significant reduc- tions in numbers of animals admitted to shelters. Animal rescue and advocacy Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
188 Fawcett organization Best Friends estimates that in the US, the number of dogs and cats killed in shelters has gradually reduced from 17 million in 1984 to 2 million in 2017 (Best Friends, 2017). However, the above figures show that many animals continue to be admit- ted to shelters, pounds and welfare organisations, and millions are killed or euthanised globally. 6 Shelters and Unintended Harm to Non-Human Animals There are some patients that we cannot help; there are none whom we cannot harm. Arthur L. Bloomfield, 1888–1962 According to David Fraser, human activities impact animals in four broad ways: 1. Keeping animals, for example as companions; 2. Causing intentional harm to animals, for example through slaughter for food; 3. Causing direct but unintended harm to animals, for example exposure to infectious disease; 4. Harming animals indirectly by disturbing life-sustaining processes and balances of nature, for example habitat destruction and anthropogenic climate change (Fraser, 2012). He developed a set of mid-level principles or what he refers to as a “practical ethic” to address ethical concerns around negative impacts of human actions on animals, and to minimize these. The principles are: 1. To provide good lives for animals in our care; 2. To treat suffering with compassion; 3. To be mindful of unseen harm; 4. To protect the life-sustaining processes and balances of nature (Fraser, 2012). While all of these principles are applicable to the animal sheltering context, for the purposes of this discussion I will focus on (3). Fraser explains that, all things being equal, it seems uncontroversial to argue that activities are of greater concern if they impact an animal over a larger proportion of its lifes- pan, and if they have long-lasting or irreversible effects. Importantly, confinement of animals in shelters gives humans control over all aspects of their lives, which provides an opportunity to provide benefits including protection from the elements, protection from risks such as motor vehicle accidents or attacks by conspecifics, nourishment, companionship, Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 189 veterinary care, and a painless death. According to Fraser, “the goal of provid- ing good lives for animals in our care should be achievable in principle, even if it would require major changes in practice” (Fraser, 2012). Whether or not these benefits are realized depends on the motivation, knowledge and resources of those working in shelters. Fraser argues that one important way that his principles differ from other common approaches to an- imal ethics is that the latter tend to focus on intentions and intentional actions rather than indirect and unintended consequences of actions (Fraser, 2012). Yet these indirect and unintended consequences can be significant, and may outweigh intended benefits. There is a growing body of literature documenting a variety of stressors for animals entering and being confined in shelters. These include leaving a familiar environment and people within it; confinement; new sounds, smells and unfamiliar animals; potential social conflict; and being handled by unfamiliar persons—usually more than one (Newbury et al., 2010). Depending on the circumstances, confinement may also entail social depriva- tion. Initially, unpredictability may lead to fear (Stephen & Ledger, 2005). Over time, predictability, monotony and confinement may lead to chronic, inescap- able boredom which is likely aversive to individual animals, and may lead to abnormal behaviour (Burn, 2017). Prolonged confinement may prevent dogs from engaging in behaviours that promote well-being, such as exercise or inter- action with humans and other dogs (Stephen & Ledger, 2005). Stress increases susceptibility to infectious disease, already a high risk in the shelter setting. Shelters have been described as “prime examples of an- thropogenic biological instability”, because they bring together animals with varying levels of disease, with often unknown health histories and exposure to different pathogens into confined spaces (Pesavento & Murphy, 2014). Stressed animals have higher rates of shedding of infectious diseases such as feline enteric coronavirus (FeCOV), feline herpesvirus, feline calicivirus, canine enteric coronavirus and other enteropathogens, some of which have zoonotic potential (Pesavento & Murphy, 2014). Emergence of fatal infectious diseases including canine influenza, haemorrhagic respiratory Escherichia coli and virulent systemic calicivirus have emerged in shelter populations, as have novel potential pathogens including canine circoviruses, bocavirus, kobuvirus and sapovirus (Pesavento & Murphy, 2014). In some instances, the use of modi- fied live vaccination in immunosuppressed animals can have adverse con- sequences (Pesavento & Murphy, 2014). Intensive housing increases risks by increasing stress, increasing the number and complexity of circulating patho- gens, as well as the possibility of direct and indirect (e.g., fomite) contact with pathogens (Pesavento & Murphy, 2014). Fomite transmission may also infect animals owned by staff members and volunteers (Schorr-Evans et al., 2003; Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
190 Fawcett Radford et al., 2007), and antimicrobial use in shelters can lead to antimicro- bial resistance (Pesavento & Murphy, 2014). Length of stay (LOS) has been identified as a risk factor for illness, including infectious disease, as well as behavioural deterioration (Newbury et al., 2010). In one study, increased LOS was associated with increased repetitive pacing and wall-bouncing (Stephen & Ledger, 2005). Other abnormal behaviours associated with kennelled dogs include tail chasing, circling, play bouncing, chewing bedding, self-licking, polydipsia, panting, lack of appetite, excessive vocalisation, listlessness, escape attempts, hiding and chewing bars (Stephen & Ledger, 2005). Because potential adopters prefer dogs who interact positively with them, abnormal behaviour may reduce the chances of adoption, increas- ing LOS (Stephen & Ledger, 2005). Many other factors can contribute to increased LOS, including barriers to adoption such as adoption fees. The long-held belief that people who pay low or no adoption fees will value their animals less has been challenged, with evidence suggesting that people whose adoption fee was waived showed no significant difference in attachment to their cat than those who paid a fee (Weiss & Gramann, 2009). Similarly, rigorous animal adoption application policies may contribute to the population surplus in shelters by reducing the pool of “acceptable” adopt- ers as many applicants do not meet the adoption criteria. Policy-based adop- tions are designed to ensure that animals are adopted into the best possible homes, and to reduce the likelihood of re-surrender. Yet in this author’s ex- perience, many “good” owners are driven to pet stores or online pet suppliers because they did not meet adoption criteria. Indeed, at the 2017 7th National G2Z Summit on the Gold Coast in Australia, only 2 out of 240 delegates—an audience consisting predominantly of those working in the animal welfare, health and management sectors—met the adoption criteria of one animal res- cue organisation. This is not the first time such an exercise has been run, with similar results (McFarland, 2014). Strategies to address such barriers have been explored. One study found that those who adopted their pet through a “conver- sation-based”, policy-free process provided similar high quality care and were likely to be just as bonded to their pet as those who adopted through policy based adoptions (Weiss et al., 2014). Creating or failing to recognise barriers to adoption that do not improve animal welfare can increase LOS and reduce the number of animals adopted, therefore constituting a harm. Long-distance animal transfer programs are increasingly employed by shel- ters to take advantage of regional differences in adoption patterns (Simmons & Hoffman, 2016). For example, a dog may be transferred from a regional Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 191 shelter to a metropolitan shelter to increase its chances of adoption. Potential unintended harms include stress associated with long distance transport, and the spread of disease, especially when organisations accepting transferred animals lack quarantine protocols (Australian Veterinary Association, 2017). Another potential harm associated with such transfers is the possibility that local animals compete with transferred animals for adoption (Simmons & Hoffman, 2016). Even established practices, such as the routine neutering of animals by shel- ters, have the potential for harm. It is argued by shelters that routine neutering of animals is the most effective means of reducing pet overpopulation, and thus the source of animals admitted to shelters. So ingrained is this belief that it has been referred to as “an article of faith within the US veterinary profes- sion: Thou shalt spay or castrate cats and dogs” (Scott Nolen, 2013). However, there is literature which suggests that there may be some detrimental impacts on the physical health and behaviour of neutered animals (Palmer et al., 2012), beyond the immediate potential morbidity and mortality related to anesthet- ic and surgical complications. Neutering may remain the lesser of two evils (overpopulation), but further evidence is required to ensure neutering-related harms are identified and minimized. As challenging as this may be, Fraser’s approach demands those who are “mindful of unseen harm” must be observant, able to articulate concerns about potential harms and give them thoughtful consideration, and willing to chal- lenge current practices. They understand that, despite their best efforts, un- seen harms will continue to exist. A current example involves dog behaviour assessments performed in shel- ters. For decades, many shelters employed animal behaviour staff with vari- ous qualifications to test dog behaviour, under the assumption that in-shelter behaviour predicts at-home behaviour. Thus, if an animal failed a behavioural evaluation for resource-guarding, it was assumed that this behaviour would be displayed post-adoption and may be a reason for future relinquishment. This could be used as justification for humane killing. But a review found that the predictive value of such evaluations was “no bet- ter than flipping a coin” (Patronek & Bradley, 2016). Displays of aggression in shelters may be context specific. The authors argue that shelters would be bet- ter off directing their resources to maximizing opportunities for staff and vol- unteers to interact with dogs “in normal and enjoyable ways that mirror what they are expected to do once adopted (e.g., walking, socializing with people, playgroups with other dogs, games, training)” (Patronek & Bradley, 2016). They argue that this, and a thorough history at admission (forming a “big- ger picture” assessment of an animal’s behaviour), would effectively enable Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
192 Fawcett shelters to vet out problem dogs, while reducing the risk of false positive re- sults for aggression in those dogs who may show aggression only in the shelter or only in the test context. Reaction to the paper has been mixed, in part because many shelters have invested heavily in developing and refining standardized behaviour assess- ments and many staff have been involved in life and death decisions made based on these assessments. The paper did not call for ditching of behavioural assessment as such, but replacement of structured assessments with multi- factorial evaluation of animals in more realistic contexts. Fraser’s framework obliges us to reevaluate current practices in the light of evidence. If animals are being harmed by being miscategorised in behavioural assessments, the practice must change. 7 Shelters and Unintended Harm to Humans I used to feel that my work was helping “save” the world. Not anymore. Anonymous shelter worker (Reeve et al., 2005) Persons working with animals are exposed to unique forms of occupational stress. In particular, the literature about occupational harms in shelter settings highlights compassion fatigue and moral stress as major concerns. Compassion fatigue may be defined as “a state of physical or psychologi- cal distress in caregivers, which occurs as a consequence of an ongoing and snowballing process in a demanding relationship with needy individuals” (van Mol et al., 2015). The term was initially used to describe a loss of compassion secondary to ongoing exposure to suffering in an occupational setting, and later defined as secondary traumatic stress resulting from deep or intense in- volvement with a person who directly experienced trauma. Thus compassion fatigue in the medical literature applies to secondary post-traumatic stress or vicarious trauma (van Mol et al., 2015). Compassion fatigue is different to burnout, as burnout is associated with occupational stress (high workload, low perceived reward, lack of autonomy) where compassion fatigue is associated with our ability to engage with others or enter into a caring relationship (with colleagues or patients). It may be ex- acerbated by work overload, lack of resources, and poor coping strategies, and may occur concurrently with burnout. A recent systematic review found that there was a general disparity of nomen- clature and variation in research methods, making it difficult to determine risk Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 193 factors, characteristics and incidence of compassion fatigue in people working with animals. However, the review found that “personnel engaged directly with euthanasia reported significantly higher levels of work stress and lower levels of job satisfaction, which may have resulted in higher employee turnover, psycho- logical distress, and other stress-related conditions” (Scotney et al., 2015). While compassion fatigue is often considered to be a direct result of eutha- nasia and humane killing, it may be induced by other occupational stressors such as client financial constraints, client non-compliance, client negligence, high workload and long-term care of patients with chronic illnesses (Scotney et al., 2015). Compassion fatigue may also be induced by moral stress. Moral distress is defined as ‘the experience of psychological distress that results from engaging in, or failing to prevent, decisions or behaviours that transgress, or come to transgress, personally held moral or ethical beliefs’ (Crane et al., 2013). It is a distinct type of occupational stress, which is an ad- verse reaction employees experience in response to pressures of the workplace (Dawson & Thompson, 2017). It differs from, for example, overwork, troubled professional relationships or the uncomplicated distress of tending to a suffer- ing animal, by the presence of conflict, between one’s own values and those of another (for example a client or employer). Situations giving rise to moral distress vary. Several studies have found that killing of healthy animals, euthanasia of sick animals, dealing with clients with financial limitations and being asked to continue treatment when you believe euthanasia is indicated are all experienced as stressful situations by veterinar- ians (Batchelor & McKeegan, 2012; Crane et al., 2015; Hartnack et al., 2016). In one study, the three ethical scenarios that veterinarians rated as “highly stress- ful” (convenience euthanasia of a healthy animal, financial limitations of cli- ents restricting treatment options, and a client pressing to continue treatment in spite of compromised animal welfare) (Batchelor & McKeegan, 2012), are common to the shelter context. This is consistent with Bernard Rollin’s account of moral stress in relation to shelter work: particularly the euthanasia of healthy or treatable animals. … [Moral] stress grows out of the radical conflict between one’s rea- sons for entering the field of animal work, and what one in fact ends up doing … imagine the psychological impact of constant demands to kill healthy animals for appalling reasons: ‘the dog is too old to run with me anymore; we have redecorated, and the dog no longer matches the colour scheme; it is cheaper to get another dog when I return from vacation than to pay the fees for a boarding kennel’, and, most perniciously, ‘I do not Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
194 Fawcett wish to spend the money on the procedure you recommend to treat the animal’ or ‘it is cheaper to get another dog’. Rollin, 2011 Scotney concurs, writing “it has been our experience that most people who work in these fields do so because they love animals and feel an affinity with them. They are rarely aware of the extent to which they will be required to kill animals” (Scotney et al., 2015). Ultimately, persons working in shelters may feel that their intention to help animals isn’t borne out in their work, and there may be a feeling of complic- ity in harm. This conflict between the values of oneself and one’s workplace presents a threat to career identity, which is particularly strong in veterinar- ians and veterinary nurses (Page-Jones & Abbey, 2015), and may be impossible to resolve. The impact of moral distress on veterinarians and shelter staff may be pro- found. According to Elizabeth Strand, founding director of the Veterinary So- cial Work program at the University of Tennessee, “handling ethical dilemmas is the most common cause of poor wellness in veterinary medicine” (Kahler, 2015). Other factors contributing to poor wellness of staff include the frequency and intensity of euthanasia, interactions with members of the public, animal cruelty, workplace conflict and “the constant stream of animals” (Kahler, 2015). The caring-killing paradox, as it has been referred to, not only causes work- place stress, but increased work-to-family conflict (incompatible demands between work and family roles that make fulfilling either role difficult), so- matic complaints (headaches, reduced appetite, pain, fatigue and so forth), substance abuse and lower levels of job satisfaction (Reeve et al., 2005). Aside from the frequency of euthanasia and killing, staff may be negatively impacted by the decision-making process itself, or the manner in which eutha- nasia and killing are carried out. In one study, shelter employee turnover rate was positively correlated with euthanasia rate, as well as the practice of mak- ing decisions to kill animals for other than health or behaviour reasons such as breed, age or pregnancy (Rogelberg et al., 2007). Shelters that had a designated room, excluded other live animals from the vicinity during euthanasia or kill- ing, and removed deceased animals from the room before another animal en- tered, had a lower staff turnover. Minimising harms to shelter staff is increasingly a legal requirement. For ex- ample, under the New South Wales Work Health and Safety Act, an employer has a primary duty “to manage risks associated with exposure to hazards aris- ing from work that could result in physical or psychological harm” (Safe Work Australia, 2014). Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 195 At its worst, an animal shelter may be harmful both to the animals confined within, as well as the staff and volunteers caring for them. The occurrence of compassion fatigue and moral stress are symptomatic of a disconnect between the values of individual staff and their role. Open discussion about the harms of compassion fatigue and moral stress have been—alongside concerns about animal welfare—significant drivers of change in shelter management. There is scant literature about the harms of shelters to members of the public. Those who surrender animals because they have no choice may suffer distress knowing that their animal may be euthanised, or that they will never know the animal’s fate. They may be judged or feel they are being judged by shelter staff (Spencer et al., 2017). This is an area that requires further explora- tion so that harms can be avoided or minimised. 8 Shelters and Unintended Harm to the Environment While the impact of the shelter environment on dogs and cats has been ex- plored in the peer reviewed literature, much of the emphasis on shelter design relates to the immediate welfare of animals within, and control of infectious disease (Newbury et al., 2010; Kiddie & Collins, 2015). An animal’s primary enclosure, surfaces and drainage, heating, ventilation, air quality, light and sound control all impact on the welfare of animals (and staff and volunteers who share the environment), but the broader environ- mental impacts of shelters remain relatively unexplored in the peer-reviewed literature. Yet these are potentially profound. For example, a poorly planned shelter could have detrimental effects on the local environment, impacting on local wildlife. Coppola and colleagues measured sound levels in a newly constructed animal shelter, and found that peak noise levels regularly exceeded the upper range of the sound level meter (118.9dBA) (Coppola et al., 2006). The paper explores the physiological and psy- chological impact of noise on dogs, but does not explore the impact on the broader environment and animals living within it. Potential environmental impacts of shelters and other animal housing facilities include but are not limited to those listed in Table 3. Addressing environmental impacts, such as noise, may benefit the wider community in which the shelter is situated, in addition to having positive im- pacts on the welfare of animals housed in the shelter, and the wellbeing of staff and volunteers. This is an area which requires more research. Similarly, euthanasia methods may have an environmental impact (Leary et al., 2013). For example, sodium pentobarbital may persist in carcases which Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
196 Fawcett Table 3 Potential environmental impacts of shelters and possible solutions Environmental impact Potential solutions Reliance on fossil fuel derived Use of renewable energy, for example active energy → CO 2 emissions solar and geothermal heating. Excessive energy use Use of energy-efficient appliances and lighting; use of natural light; use of timers; tinted glass to minimise heat loss in winter and maximise heat gain in summer. Water use Use of low-flow water fixtures, landscaping with drought-resistant plants, reclaiming grey water, use of artificial turf in dog toileting areas, collecting rainwater. Waste Recycling, composting, reducing single-item packaging through bulk buying. Recycled building materials may also be used. Chemical and toxic waste Use of environmentally friendly cleaning products; use of digital radiography and thermometers, use of low to no volatile organic compound paint. Build-up of noxious gases such as Design buildings to provide optimal ventilation ammonia Disruption of natural habitats Building shelters on existing sites; reduce soil erosion using a sedimentation control plan. Environmental impact of visitors Provide public transport options, preferred and staff parking for low-emission vehicles Compiled from American Veterinary Medical Association (2017), Pittman (2016) and Islam et al. (2016) can contaminate the environment or cause secondary toxicity in animals that feed on carcases which are exposed or become exposed (Kaiser et al., 2010; Col- lege of Veterinarians of British Columbia, 2014). From a purely utilitarian perspective, if addressing environmental impacts can minimise harm and maximise animal welfare (both those within and in the vicinity of shelters), people (shelter staff and the wider community), and environmental wellbeing, this should be pursued. This is an area that warrants extensive further study. Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
One Welfare Approach 197 9 The One Welfare Approach to Animal Shelters The previous discussion outlines potential, unintended harms to animals, hu- mans and the environment associated with animal shelters. The One Welfare framework first appeared in the veterinary literature in 2013, where it was ar- gued that “global ethical and policy decisions about human and animal welfare should be based on the consideration of the wellbeing of animals and humans within their ecosystem” (Colonius & Earley, 2013). In 2017 the World Organisation for Animal Health (OIE) developed its Global Animal Welfare Strategy, aiming for “a world where the welfare of ani- mals is respected, promoted and advanced, in ways that complement the pur- suit of animal health, human well-being, socio-economic development and environmental sustainability” (OIE, 2017a). The Strategy acknowledges the close and often inextricable links between animal welfare, animal health, the health and well-being of people, and the sustainability of socio-economic and ecological systems (OIE, 2017a). Consider the example of an overcrowded open-admission shelter with poor animal welfare, poor staff well-being and practices with a high environ- mental impact. One way to reduce shelter-related harms to animals, humans and the en- vironment is for shelters to determine and operate within their “capacity for care”. According to the Association of Shelter Veterinarians, “every sheltering organisation has a maximum capacity for care, and the population in their care must not exceed that level” (Newbury et al., 2010). Working within that capacity for care can reduce overpopulation and staff stress levels, reducing harms to humans and animals. In addition, there are benefits. One study found that application of a “capacity for care” management system in the feline section of three shelters improved LRR, decreased death rates and reduced the number of cats requiring isolation (often associated with increased LOS) (Karsten et al., 2017). Lowering the total number of ani- mals housed on a daily basis increased the total number of animals rehomed while reducing resource requirements (Karsten et al., 2017), which may have a positive environmental impact. The reduction of euthanasia rates may reduce compassion fatigue and moral stress. In addition, the teaching of communication skills, ethical rounds to discuss ethical aspects of cases and mindfulness are interventions that have been suggested to combat compassion fatigue and moral stress (van Mol et al., 2015), yet their success in doing so, and how this impacts animal welfare, has not been evaluated in a shelter or veterinary context. Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1 (2019) 177–208 Downloaded from Brill.com09/14/2021 12:26:39PM via free access
You can also read