TOPICALIZATION AND OTHER PUZZLES OF GERMAN SYNTAX1
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
TOPICALIZATION AND OTHER PUZZLES OF GERMAN SYNTAX1 Hubert Haider, Dept. of Linguistics, Univ. of Stuttgart 1990 [in G. Grewendorf & W.Sternefeld eds. Scrambling and Barriers. Amsterdam: Benjamins. p. 93-112] Abstracts. This paper analyzes the syntactic properties of sentences with a V-projection in clause initial position, so-called VP-topicalization. The analysis pursues two theoretic claims. First, it will be claimed that this construction provides an argument for a representational conception of Generative Grammar (cf. Koster 1987) and against the standard GB-model with derivation by movement. It will be shown that VP-topicalization defies a derivational analysis. Secondly, this construction provides evidence for the claim that in German the subject is internal to V-max. In section 2, the relevant syntactic aspects of the construction are introduced. Section 3 provides arguments that a movement analysis cannot capture the relevant generalizations. A representational account is presented in section 4, together with an expla- nation of the syntactic behavior described in section 2. Section 5 discusses some consequences of the representational account. 1 I am grateful to Klaus Netter for comments and criticism. It was his observation that pronouns in the Wacker- nagel position (cf. examples in (12)) behave differently. 1
1. INTRODUCTION The two main issues dealt with in this paper are i) arguments for a representational concept of syntactic representations instead of a derivational one, and ii) arguments in favor of an inclusive verbal projection for German, i.e. a VP that contains the subject. The data on which the argu- ments are based is a common construction of German, the topicalization of a verbal projection: (1) [CP [Einen Blinden geführt]i [C' hatj [X-max ein Einäugiger ei ej]]] a blind one guided has a one-eyed ‘A one-eyed has guided a blind one’ According to a current derivational analysis (cf. den Besten 1983), (1) is the product of two instances of movement: the finite Verb moves to the C-position, and a phrase moves to the SPEC-C-position. SPEC-C can host only one phrase, and it must be a maximal projection (cf. Chomsky 1986). Under a representational analysis, the verbal projection would be generated in SPEC-C and coindexed with an empty category in the functional base position. It will turn out that the latter approach is empirically superior to the former. As to the status of V-max, an SOV language like German or Dutch is in principle open for one of two types of verbal projections. Either the subject is external to VP, like in English (exclu- sive VP) or the subject is part of the VP (inclusive VP). There are independent arguments (cf. Haider 1986, 1989a) that the VP in Dutch is exclusive whereas it is inclusive in German. The analysis of topicalization will support this claim. Upon first sight, however, it seems to provide an argument for an exclusive VP: (2) *[Ein Einäugiger geführt] hat einen Blinden a one-eyed guided has a blind (a one-eyed has guided a blind) It is tempting to try to account for the difference between (1) and (2) in terms of the constituent structure of VP. In (1) a VP seems to be topicalized, while in (2) the subject together with the verb appears in front, with the object left behind. Since the subject does not form a constituent with the verb that excludes the object, (2) is illformed, because fronting of the subject and the verb would encompass the object too. This account is too simple, however, as the examples in (3) reveal. (3) a. [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen] hat hier noch nie b. [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen] hat es hier noch nie (es = z.B. das Derby) c. [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen] scheint hier noch nie zu haben d. [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen zu haben] scheint hier noch nie In each sentence a non-ergative subject is part of the verbal projection. In (3b) we find in addi- tion an object left behind, and in (3c,d) the subject is part of a verbal projection that contains even a raising verb. The most exotic kind of evidence comes from split NPs, as illustrated in (4). (4) a. [Briefe geschrieben] hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige b. [Außenseiter gewonnen] hat es bis jetzt nur ein einziger 2
What we find in the initial position is the verb together with the head of an NP, with the rest of the NP at the end of the sentence. It will turn out that there is no movement process that could strip an NP of its head and move it to the front, together with the verb. In the following section I will present evidence for the claim that the topicalized verbal projection is base generated in its topic position. 2. SOME EMPIRICAL ISSUES The observations discussed in this section are organized under a particular perspective. I choose constructions for which the topicalized V-projection displays properties which do not obtain to its base position. Since these properties would be conserved under movement, however, they should be found in the base position, too. This will be taken as evidence for an analysis which assumes the topicalized projection to be base-generated in SPEC-C (see section 4). 2.1 Extraposition An extraposed clause is usually taken to be adjoined either to VP or S, depending on its argu- ment status (cf. Reinhart 1983). As shown in (5a,c) and (6a) an extraposed clause may be ad- joined to the topicalized V-projection. (5) a. [Fragen, ob wir einverstanden sind] wird er wohl müssen b.*daß er wohl fragen, ob wir einverstanden sind, müssen wird c. [Schreiben, daß er nicht kommen darf] hat er nicht mehr können d.*daß er nicht mehr hat schreiben, daß er nicht kommen darf, können e. daß er nicht mehr hat schreiben können, daß er nicht kommen darf (6) a. [Hunde füttern, die Hunger haben], würde wohl jeder b.*daß wohl jeder [Hunde füttern, die Hunger haben] würde c. daß wohl jeder [Hunde, die Hunger haben], füttern würde d. daß wohl jeder Hunde füttern würde, die Hunger haben Since the extraposed variant with extraposition cannot occur in the base position (cf. 5b,d; 6b), extraposition must take place in the topicalized position, i.e. after topicalization. In this case, however, it cannot be maintained anymore that there are different positions for extraposed rela- tive clauses in contrast with extraposed argument clauses. Both are adjoined to the same V- projection (cf. 5a,c and 6a). There is still one more problematic consequence for a derivational analysis. In a finite clause, the V-projection to which the extraposed clause is adjoined contains the finite Verb (cf. 6d). Hence we would expect that a clause which is extraposed out of a topi- calized V-projection is adjoined to the VP of the matrix clause. Thus we would get (7) instead of (5a). (7) Fragen wird er wohl müssen, ob wir einverstanden sind (7) could be generated also if extraposition is applied before topicalization. Since we do not want to have ordered rules, this is what we would like to find. Since (5a,c) and (6) exist never- theless, they must be deriveable. Of course, one could assume that the topicalized V-projection originally contained the finite verb, which afterwards moved to the C-position, leaving a trace behind: (8) [Gesungen ei] hati er 3
Unfortunately, a derivation of the type (8) must not be permitted. If it were possible, we would get sentences like (9), which are ungrammatical. (9) a.*[Ihr ein Buch ei] gabi Hans b.*[Ein Buch auf ei] schlugi Hans Hence we end up with a construction for which there is no satisfactory account in terms of VP- movement, i.e. in derivation-by-movement terms. 2.2 Definiteness effect It has been noted by Kratzer (1984) that Vn -topicalization is affected by the definiteness effect, if a subject, ergative or unergative, is part of the projection. (10)a. Ein Fehler unterlaufen ist ihr noch nie b.??Dieser Fehler unterlaufen ist ihr noch nie c. daß ihr dieser Fehler noch nie unterlaufen ist d. Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat hier noch nie e.??Der Außenseiter gewonnen hat hier noch nie f. daß hier noch nie der Außenseiter gewonnen hat (11) a. There arrived a man from Rio b.??There arrived the man from Rio c. Es dirigierte Herbert von Karajan d. Es gewann die Mannschaft aus Schweden (11c,d) exemplify that in German there is no definiteness comparable to the one in English or Dutch in existential or presentative clauses. Again, if it is just a VP that is moved to the front, it is unclear why this VP should gain new properties. 2.3. Subjects within the topicalized projection Subjects may appear in the topicalized V-projection precisely under two conditions, which have to be captured by the derivational account. First, the subject must be non-referential (definite- ness effect). Secondly, an unergative subject may appear in the fronted V-projection provided that there is at most one argument left behind which occurs immediately after the finite verb (cf. 12b vs. 12c). It is this property alone, which discriminates ergative and unergative subjects (cf. 12b vs. 13a). (12) a. Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat da noch nie b.*Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat da noch nie das Derby c. Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat das da noch nie d. Linguisten gespeist haben dort noch nie e.*Linguisten gespeist haben dort noch nie Langusten f. Linguisten gespeist haben das dort noch nie g. Kinder gespielt haben hier noch nie h.*Kinder gespielt haben hier noch nie Tempelhüpfen i. Kinder gespielt haben das hier noch nie (13) a. Ein Fehler unterlaufen ist auch schon mal diesem Professor b. Ein Fehler unterlaufen ist ihm auch schon mal 4
c. Ein Tiger entwichen ist doch erst kürzlich diesem Wanderzirkus d. Ein Tiger entwichen ist ihm doch erst kürzlich In (12) I chose three transitive verbs with an optional direct object. If the subject is part of the topicalized constituent, the object cannot appear in its base position after the adverbials (cf. 12b,e,h). Ergative subjects behave differently (cf. 13a,c). Ergative subjects pattern in this con- struction like passive subjects, as expected. (14) a. Ein Job angeboten wurde damals sofort jedem Tagträumer b. Ein Job angeboten wurde ihm damals sofort It will be made clear in the following section that the differences noted above cannot be cap- tured adequately under a derivational approach employing scrambling. 2.4 Inconsistent structure requirements If one takes the premises seriously that only maximal projections appear in the SPEC-C posi- tion and that only one projection can be moved to this position, topicalization structures reflect inconsistent structure assignment requirements. (15) a. daß er ihren Argumenten folgen können wird b. Ihren Argumenten folgen wird er doch wohl können c. folgen können wird er ihren Argumenten doch wohl According to (15b) we would like to project structure (16a) on (15a), but on the example (15c) we would like to choose (16b). (16) a. [[seinen Argumenten folgen] können] b. [seinen Argumenten [folgen können]] One might try to stick to (16a) and derive (15c) by string-vacuous Chomsky-adjunction of the object to its mother VP and move the emptied VP. This move would still leave it mysterious, however, how (17a) and (17b) could be tackled. (17) a. [Ein Außenseiter gewinnen] hätte hier wohl kaum können b. [Gewinnen können] hätte ein Außenseiter hier wohl kaum (17a) requires a structure in which the modal takes an S-complement, which is fronted. In order to derive (17b), the subject must be Chomsky-adjoined again to its mother constituent, the S, such that the emptied constituent contains only the modal. This cannot be the case, however, since S would contain also the adverbials and the finite verb, too. It is shown above that this would give rise to a construction like (9) and therefore has to be abandoned. This leaves (17) without a derivational source. 2.5 Topicalization of non-constituents As pointed out in section 1, split NPs pose a serious problem for a derivational analysis, if they appear within a verbal projection. For convenience, the examples (4) are repeated under (18). (18) a. [Briefe geschrieben] hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige b. [Außenseiter gewonnen] hat es bis jetzt nur ein einziger (18) is the VP-topicalization variant of (19). 5
(19) a. Briefe hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige geschrieben b. Außenseiter hat es bis jetzt nur ein einziger gewonnen The characteristics of constructions of the type (19) are the following. The element in SPEC-C must be the head of the split NP (cf. 20a). The NP must be indefinite (cf. (20b). The NP con- tains a gap (cf. 20c). The relation between the two parts obeys movement constraints (cf. 21).2 (20) a.*Nur drei traurige hat sie mir bis jetzt Briefe geschrieben b.*Briefe hat sie mir bis jetzt nur die drei traurigen geschrieben c.*Briefe hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige Episteln geschrieben (21) a. Bücher sagte man mir, habe er nur politische geschrieben b.*Bücher sagte man mir, wer nur politische geschrieben habe c.*Bücher nannte sie mir einen Mann, der nur politische geschrieben hat The fact that (19) does not permit a split variant in the base position, bars a movement account for (18). (22) a.*daß sie nur drei traurige bis jetzt Briefe geschrieben hat b.*daß es nur ein einziger bis jetzt Außenseiter gewonnen hat There is no V-projection consisting of the head of an NP and the verb. 2.6 Scope asymmetries3 (23) shows, that scope properties are subject to reconstruction. (23) a. daß Max jemandem kein Buch verkaufen darf b. Max darfi [jemanden kein Buch verkaufen ei] Both in (23a) and in (23b) the negation may have scope over the modal. This can be accounted for by reconstruction: Since the trace of the modal is in the scope of the negation this carries over to the antecedent. That the middle field, i.e. the constituent in brackets in (23b) constrains the scope domain can be seen from (24): (24) a. daß jedem Lehrer ein Schüler gefallen möchte (narrow, wide) b. daß ein Schüler jedem Lehrer gefallen möchte (narrow, wide) c. [Jedem Schüler gefallen] möchte ein Lehrer (wide) To account for (24), we have to assume both that the middle filed restricts the scope domain (as in 23), to keep the existential quantifier in a narrow scope and we have to assume that the topi- calized constituent does not reconstruct. Otherwise we would expect the same scope properties as in (24a,b). If (24c) is derived by movement we expect reconstruction, however. 2.7 Independent evidence for base generated V-projections Left-dislocation provides evidence that there are base-generated V-projections in non-base posi- tions on the one hand, and that there are differences between left-dislocation and topicalization 2 Henk van Riemsdijk discussed these constraints in his talk given at the Workshop on Dialectology in Venice, April 1, 1987. In V-projection structures of the type (18) the remnant of the NP tends to be clause final, i.e. imme- diately adjacent to the gap the V-projection in SPEC-C is coindexed with. This information I owe to Gosse Bou- ma, personal communication. 3 These data I owe to T.Höhle, who discussed them in a talk given at the GGS-workshop Konstanz, November 1986. 6
on the other hand that provide insight into the nature of the dependency between the left periph- eral position, be it SPEC-C or the LD-position, and its functionally equivalent clause internal position. Since the dependency is different, it is unlikely that one can be derived from the other, as suggested e.g. by Koster (1978). The following sample of contexts is sufficient to dismiss the claim that topicalization is derived from left-dislocation simply by replacing the pronoun in the SPEC-C Position by an empty operator. (25)a. anaphor: Sich (*den) mag er am liebsten [AP stolz auf sich] (das) war er schon immer b.quantifier Jeder (*der) weiß das c. indefinite pronoun Jemand (*der) hat sich geirrt d.sentential adverb Vermutlich (*das) weiß er es e. predicatives4 Stumm (*das) lächelt Mona Lisa f. NP-subconstituents Linguisten (*die) kenne ich nur kluge g. Extraposition out of a topicalized V-projection Rosen gezüchtet, (*das) hat er die prämiert wurden h.V-projection with subcategorized elements Gewartet (*das) hat er auf sie nicht i. Split NPs in V-projections Briefe geschrieben (*das) hat sie drei traurige j. V-Projections that contain a non-ergative subject Ein Außenseiter gewonnen (*das) hat hier noch nie These differences call for an explanation in terms of the syntactic relation that holds between the non-base position and the functional base position. For topicalization this relation is an an- tecedent-empty category relation, for LD, however, it is a relation between a phrase and a pro- nominal element it is coindexed with. Whatever account is given for this difference, this does not concern the fact that in LD-constructions we find verbal projections generated in non-base positions: (26) a. [Ihr Blumen geschenkt] (das) hat er noch nie b. [Ein Buch lesen] (das) würde er nie c. Gelogen (das) hat er noch nie d. Geregnet (das) hat es schon lange nicht mehr 3. SCRAMBLING - AN INADEQUATE SOLUTION There are some recent attempts (cf. den Besten & Webelhut 1990) to revive Ross's idea how to handle free word order, namely by employing the concept of scrambling. Scrambling is inter- preted as the result of free adjunction to VP, a concept introduced by Chomsky (1986) in the 4 Marga Reis, personal communication. 7
framework of "Barriers". According to a scrambling-based approach the topicalized V- projection in (27) is V-max in all cases: (27) a. [ ei ej geöffnet] hat sie ihmi die Augenj b. [ ei die Augen geöffnet] hat sie ihm ei c. [ihm die Augen geöffnet] hat sie In order to derive (27), the objects must be moved out of the VP. Adjunction of the objects to VP should leave a preposable empty VP. The result is (28) as a base structure for (27a). (28) [CP [C´ [VP sie [VP ihmi [VP die Augenj [VP ei ej geöffnet ]]] hat]]] It is easy to demonstrate that scrambling-by-adjunction is both too strong and too weak a con- cept. It is too strong because it overgenerates and it is too weak because there are topicalization structures which cannot be derived by means of scrambling. Let us start with the case of over- generation: A scrambling approach neither captures the definiteness effect (cf. 2.2) nor the subject-object dependency discussed in section 2.3. (29) shows that objects may appear in front of a definite subject. This means that the object is adjoined to S, which turns the basic S into a candidate for topicalization: (29) a. daß den Mann die Kinder nicht gestört haben b.*[Die Kinder gestört] haben den Mann nicht The fact that a subject may appear in the topicalized projection only if the remaining object - in case there is one - appears in front of the middle field does not follow from the way how scrambling works. For convenience, I repeat an example illustrating the relevant contrast: (30) a. Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat dieses Jahr noch nie b.*Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat dieses Jahr noch nie das Derby c. Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat es dieses Jahr noch nie For (30b) there exists a perfectly well-formed scrambled base-variant as a source for topicaliza- tion: (31) a. daß ein Außenseiter dieses Jahr noch nie das Derby gewonnen hat b. daß das Derby ein Außenseiter dieses Jahr noch nie gewonnen hat c. daß dieses Jahr noch nie das Derby ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat First the object is adjoined to S, which yields (31b). Then the adverbials are adjoined, which yields (31c). Now the emptied S-constituent is topicalized, which yields the ungrammatical (30b). Scrambling is to weak for the derivation of the split-NP cases. For (32) there is no source for topicalization because splitting an NP by scrambling is ungrammatical, cf. (19a), (18a) and (22a), repeated under (32a), (32b) and (32c) respectively. (32) a. Briefe hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige geschrieben b. [Briefe geschrieben] hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige c.*daß sie mir nur drei traurige bis jetzt Briefe geschrieben hat 8
(32c) shows that the NP cannot be split within the middle field. A sentence like (33) would re- quire a base structure like (32c). (33) [Briefe geschrieben] hat sie mir nur drei traurige bis jetzt Scrambling is too weak, moreover, because it is completely unclear under that hypothesis why the topicalized V-Projection is an extraposition site (cf. sect. 2.1). It is too weak also because it overgenerates, if V-projections are topicalized that contain the finite verb.5 (34)*[Ihr ein Buch ei] schenktei er. The ungrammaticality of (34) cannot be attributed to the fact that the projection contains the trace of the finite verb, because exactly this trace occurs in the case of what would be an S- topicalization: (35) [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen ei] hati hier noch nie Since the topicalized constituent contains the subject, it must be topicalization of S. S, however, is IP and hence contains the finite verb. Scrambling is too strong again, because it rules out per- fectly well-formed structures in the case of coordination: (36) weil esi entweder [niemand ei bemerkte] oder [Maria alle bestochen hat] Under a scrambling analysis (36) violates the Across-the-board constraint, which forbids con- joining a phrase containing a gap with another phrase that does not contain a corresponding gap. Scrambling leaves a gap in the base position. Finally it should be noted that a scrambling approach towards topicalization frequently involves vacuous movement. In (37) the object is string-vacuously adjoined to VP in order to turn the topicalized element into a VP. Chomsky (1986) provided arguments against vacuous movement, which can be strengthened (cf. Haider 1989b) to a complete ban. (37) [ei geholfen]j hat [sie [VP ihri [VP e]j In the following section I will try to show that all these problems do not arise if we give up the idea that topicalization is the result of a movement process. 4. TOWARDS A REPRESENTATIONAL ACCOUNT OF TOPICALIZATION Let us suppose that the V-projection in the SPEC-C position is base-generated in this very posi- tion just like the V-projection is base-generated in LD-constructions. These two constructions differ with respect to the relation they enter with the functional base position. For topicalization it is an antecedent - gap relation, for LD it is an antecedent - pronominal relation. The pronomi- nal in (26) acts as a predicate pronominal whose interpretation is determined by the predicate it is coindexed with. If there is no predicate, the pronominal is interpreted deictically (cf. 26 and 38). (38) a. Das hat er noch nie b. Das würde er nie c. Das hat er noch nie d. Das hat es schon lange nicht mehr 5 This has been noted by Jindrich Toman, in the discussion period. 9
Semantically, the verbal projection in an LD-construction is interpreted as an autonomous pred- icate, whose interpretation determines the interpretation of the pronominal it is coindexed with. The analogous analysis for topicalization entails that the topicalized V-projection is interpreted as an autonomous predicate, too, i.e. as a maximal projection of V. In LF this V-projection will receive a semantic interpretation in its SPEC-C position. Since the topicalized phrase enters into an antecedent - gap relation by virtue of its occupying the SPEC-C position, the predicate in SPEC-C position will be related to the matrix predicate as if the topicalized predicate were a single verb: (39) Vi hatj er nicht [VC [ ei ] ej]] The only well-formedness requirements for the verbal projection in (39) are a syntactic one and a functional-semantic one. It must be a maximal projection and it must provide a Θ-role for the subject in the middle field. Hence any of the following instances of Vn will give a grammatical sentence in the context of (39): (40) a. getanzt b. mir geholfen c. mich absichtlich geohrfeigt d. ihr heimlich einen Kuß gegeben e. ihr einen Kuß auf die Wange gedrückt, daß es schnalzte From a semantic point of view, these are intransitive predicates. Some are basically intransitive (40a), some are intransitive due to saturation of all argument slots except one. Hence they fulfill the functional requirement of the gap the predicate in (39) is coindexed with. It is the gap of an intransitive verb, a gap that would arise if we inserted a verb like (40a) and moved it to the SPEC-C position. We could not insert the other predicates, however, since it is the slot of a V° category in the verbal cluster. The verbal cluster does not contain phrases. Hence these phrases do not have a derivational source. Let us investigate now how this hypothesis allows handling the recalcitrant problems discussed in section 2 and 3. 4.1 Extraposition In German, and presumably in all other languages as well, Vmax is the adjunction site for extra- position, both for clausal arguments and non-arguments. Claims that different binding proper- ties require different adjunction sites (cf. Reinhart 1983) are ill-founded. It is not the adjunction position that matters but the argument status. Principle C violations do not arise, despite of a c- commanding, preceding, coindexed NP, if the noun is contained in a non-argument clause. This is easy to see in German, where adverbials and likewise adverbial clauses appear between an object and the verb, i.e. VP-internal: (41) a. Der Vorsitzende hat ihri [obwohl Mariei heftig protestierte] das Wort entzogen b. daß eri [als man Hansi davon berichtete] kollabierte, wundert mich nicht c. Man hat ihmi mehr Geld als Hansi sich erwartet hatte angeboten d. Man hat ihri das Haus, das Mariai bekanntlich geerbt hat, streitig gemacht Non-argument clauses are opaque for principle C. Viewed from this perspective, it is not sur- prising that relative clauses are adjoined to the same V-projection in the topicalized position as object clauses; they are adjoined to the same projection in the base position as well. The V- 10
projection in SPEC-C position is a maximal V-projection and hence an adjunction site for ex- traposition. 4.2 Definiteness Effect A definiteness effect is found whenever a subject does not appear in its canonical position. This is easy to check for English. In a there-construction, the thematic subject appears VP-internally, in a non-canonical subject-position. In German, the canonical subject position is in the middle field and not in a V-Projection in SPEC-C. Hence the topicalized V-projection displays a defi- niteness effect for the subject. The fact that there is no definiteness effect in the middle field simply shows that any position in the middle field qualifies as canonical position for a subject. This is to be expected if German has an inclusive VP. 4.3 Subjects within the topicalized VP If the topicalized VP contains a subject, it must be non-referential, i.e. indefinite and, if it is non-ergative, its co-argument must not occur inside the middle-field. This follows from a clo- sure property induced by non-ergative subjects. (42) The verbal projection that contains the non-ergative subject is closed for the projection principle What (42) amounts to is that a Θ-role cannot be passed on to an argument outside a VP that contains a non-ergative subject. Hence in the example (43) the object remains Θ-less and vio- lates the Θ-criterion. (43) *Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat da noch nie das Derby (cf. 12b) What is the difference between (43) and (44) that allows maintaining (42), although the object is not in the same V-projection? (44) Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat das da noch nie (cf. 12c) There is one possibility, how the object might receive a Θ-role, namely by means of a chain: (45) [Ein Außenseiter ei gewonnen] hat dasi da noch nie What we have to explain now is why a chain is possible in (45) but not in (43). The answer is simple. In (44) the pronoun occupies the so-called Wackernagel-position, a position that imme- diately follows C. This is an adjunction position of the middle field. It is easy to show, that the c-command requirement for the antecedent of the gap can only be met in that position and not in the base position, which will explain the difference between (43) and (44). All we have to do is to adapt the definition of dominance to adjunction structures. According to Chomsky (1986), adjunction produces segments of categories. (46) [XP Y [XP Z ]] (adjunction of Y to XP) In (46), XP consists of two segments. Given that a category C includes an element E, if every segment of C dominates E, Z is included by XP, but Y is not. Now it is easy to adjust domi- nance to adjunction: (47) a. A category C c-dominates X, iff C includes X b. A c-commands B iff 11
a. A does not c-dominate B and b. every maximal projection that c-dominates A c-dominates B (47) is a conservative extension of the original definitions, since in non-adjunction structures inclusion coincides with domination? The difference between (43) and (44) follows immediately from (47): It is only in the Wackernagel-position, not in the base position, that an object can c-command an empty catego- ry in SPEC-C, because for the element in that position CP is the only maximal projection that includes it and CP dominates the gap. The difference between this account and the scrambling account is clear. Under the latter hypothesis, both the adverbial and the object would be in ad- joined position and hence the object should be able to c-command, which is obviously not the case, as (48) illustrates:6 (48)*Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat da noch nie das Derby (cf. 12b) 4.4 Inconsistent structure assignments The problem of inconsistent structure requirements arises only under the movement analysis. If a V-projection is base-generated in SPEC-C, it can be any V-projection, provided it meets the functional requirements imposed on it by the kind of arguments that appear in the middle field. (49) a. Ihren Argumenten folgen wird er doch wohl können (cf. 15b) b. Folgen können wird er ihren Argumenten doch wohl (cf. 15c) In (49a) the topicalized V-projection can be replaced by any intransitive predicate, i.e. anything that is functionally equivalent, e.g. by the intransitive variant of ‘folgen’, as in (50a). In (49b) the functional properties are not affected by the modal, hence its omission would lead to (50b). (50) a. Folgen wird er doch wohl können b. Folgen wird er ihren Argumenten doch wohl Since this account is not bound to the assumption that the topicalized V-projection must corre- spond to an isomorphic structure in the base position before movement, the structural paradox cannot arise. 4.5 Topicalization of non-constituents The definiteness affect observed with this construction indicates that the head noun in the V- projection is interpreted as a predicate. Evidence to this end comes from (51). (51) a. [Briefe geschrieben] hat sie nie welche b.*daß sie nie welche Briefe geschrieben hat c. daß sie nie welche geschrieben hat 6 Günther Grewendorf, p.c., noted that (48) can be improved if the object precedes the adverbial and carries focus stress: i) Ein Außenseiter gewonnen hat das DERBY hier noch nie The difference between i) and (48) follows immediately if it is recognized that the focus position for non- pronominal NPs coincides with the Wackernagel-position. Then the analysis given for (45) carries over to i) as well. 12
The indefinite pronoun ’welche’ represents an NP. Hence it will receive the Θ-role from the verb. But then no Θ-role is left for the noun ’Briefe’ in (51a), which cannot be part of the ob- ject-NP, as (51b) shows. If it does not receive a é-role it cannot be an argument but only a pred- icate. This seems to match the interpretation of (51a). ’Briefe’ specifies the denotation of the pronoun just like in (52). (52) Das sind Briefe It seems that the role of ’Briefe’ in (51a) is the same as in (53). (53) [Briefe geschrieben] hat sie mir bis jetzt nur drei traurige The noun restricts the denotation of the element the Θ-role is assigned to but it does not bear it. Thus it does not close the V-projection even if it is in relation with a non-ergative subject, as in (54). If the head of the subject NP in the V-projection would close it, the remnant of the NP could not get its Θ-role.7 (54) [Außenseiter gewonnen] hat es bis jetzt nur ein einziger The fact that the noun serves as a predicate correlates with the fact that it cannot appear without a concomitant NP that it agrees with. It is licensed only under predication (cf. 55) (55) a.*[Außenseiter gewonnen] hat es bis jetzt nicht8 b.*[Außenseiter gewonnen] das hat es bis jetzt nur ein einziger In (55a) there is no phrase the noun is coindexed with, and in (55b) the phrase it should be coindexed with is not accessible. 4.6 Scope asymmetries If the topicalized VP is base-generated in SPEC-C the sope properties become transparent. We can explain why (56c) does not have the same sope properties as (56a,b). (56) a. daß Max jemandem kein Buch verkaufen darf (NEG: narrow or wide) b. Max darf jemandem kein Buch verkaufen (NEG: narrow or wide) c. Jemandem kein Buch verkaufen darf Max (NEG: narrow) Scope is constrained by the VP. In (56a) and (56b) the negation and the modal share the same VP. In (56c) the negation is contained in a VP different from the VP that contains the modal. Hence the negation does not have scope over the modal outside its V-projection. 4.7. Crossing constraint The scrambling analysis suffers from an explanatory deficiency. It is unclear why there shows up a crossing effect in some cases (cf. 58) and not in others (cf. 57) (57) a. [ei ej geöffnet]k hat sie ihmi die Augenj ek b. [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen ei] hati hier noch nie 7 That the V-projection is not closed at all, neither for the Θ-role of the subject nor for that of an object is illustrat- ed by (i.): [Außenseiter gewonnen] haben bis jetzt ein Derby nur wenige 8 It is relevant here, that the NP is singular in number. So we know that Außenseiter is a noun and not an NP, since the NP requires an article. This is different for the plural. In i) Außenseiter is an NP without article, hence i) is wellformed. i) Außenseiter gewonnen haben bis jetz noch nie 13
(58) a.*[Ihr ein Buch ei] schenktei er b.*[ei mit]PP haben sie dai nicht gerechnet c. Dai haben sie nicht [ei mit]PP gerechnet Under the base generation hypothesis, (58a,b) but not (57a,b) turn out to be violations of a crossing constraint: (60) a. [Geöffnet]k hati sie ihm die Augen ek ei (cf. (57a) b. [Ein Außenseiter gewonnen]j hati hier noch nie ej ei (cf.57b) c. [Ihr ein Buch ei]j schenktei er ej ei d. [ei mit] haben sie dai ej nicht gerechnet In (60c,d), but not in (60a,b) we observe a particular type of crossing dependences, which are ruled out on independent grounds (cf. Pesetzky 1982). In (60a,b) the two dependencies are dif- ferent in type, a head-movement dependency and a phrase movement dependency. Hence cross- ing is irrelevant. In (60c,d), however, we find crossing dependencies of the same type, which is ruled out. 5. SOME REQUIREMENTS FOR AND CONSEQUENCES OF A REPRESENTATIONAL ACCOUNT The claim that V-Projections are base-generated in SPEC-C requires some clarifications as to how case- and Θ-assignment applies. The fact that there are VP internal nominatives under any analysis in a Government & Binding framework (cf. den Besten 1985) irrespective of the par- ticular assumptions about the canonical position of the subject should suffice to indicate that VP-internal NPs are accessible for nominative assignment for reasons independent from our present concern. Therefore I will not elaborate on that matter. What is unique for the present claim, however, is that a clause may have two independent V- projections and that the verb in one projection may assign Θ-roles to arguments in the other projection. The crucial concept for handling this situation is the syntactic role of auxiliaries. In Haider/Rindler-Schjeve (1987) and in Haider (1986), I tried to demonstrate that the finite verb is the syntactic main verb of the clause. Auxiliaries can act syntactically as main verbs by virtue of the transfer of the argument structure from the verb they govern in the verbal complex to the auxiliary. This mechanism applies without further complications to the topicalized V- projection, since they are coindexed with a verbal empty category in the base position that is c- commanded by the auxiliary. Under this perspective there is no direct transfer of the Θ-roles from the verb in the topicalized projection to the arguments in the middle field just like there is no direct assignment of Θ-roles from the main verb to the arguments in the middle field. In both cases it is the auxiliary which mediates the Θ-role assignment and case assignment. One of the consequences of the representational account is that German has an inclusive VP, i.e. a V-projection that contains the subject. Since it is beyond dispute that Dutch does not have an inclusive VP, we predict specific differences for the topicalization structures. Topicalized V- projections that contain unergative subjects cannot occur in Dutch since non-ergative subjects cannot occur in V-Projections in Dutch. The following examples confirm this claim: (61) a. *Een buitenstaander gewonnen heeft daar nog nooit (cf.12a) b. *Linguisten gegeten hebben daar nog nooit (cf.12b) c. *Kinderen gespeeld hebben hier nog nooit (cf. 12c) 14
This difference falls in line with a lot of other systematic differences between subjects in Ger- man and in Dutch (cf. Haider 1986, 1989a) that receive an explanation in terms of the different status of V-max in the respective languages. 6. CONCLUSION The aim of this paper is twofold. From the empirical point of view, it presents an analysis that covers the properties of topicalized V-projections. Topicalized V-projections are base-generated in SPEC-C. From the theoretical point of view, it is argued that the analysis of this construc- tions provides arguments for i) a representational view instead of a derivational one, and ii) an inclusive VP in German, i.e. a V-max that contains the subject, unlike the English or Dutch VP. A scrambling analysis is dismissed on empirical grounds. BIBLIOGRAPHY BESTEN, H. DEN 1983. On the interaction of root transformations and lexical deletive rules. In W. Abraham (Ed.), On the Formal Syntax of the Westgermania, Amsterdam: John Ben- jamins. (p. 47–131) BESTEN,H. DEN & G.WEBELHUTH 1990. (this volume). Stranding. In G. Grewendorf & W. Sternefeld eds. Scrambling and Barriers. Amsterdam: Benjamins. (p.77-92) CHOMSKY,N. 1986. Barriers. Cambridge,Mass.: MIT-Press HAIDER,H. 1986. Deutsche Syntax, generativ - Parameter der deutschen Syntax. Habilita- tionsschrift. Universität Wien. HAIDER,H. 1989a. Θ-tracking systems - evidence from German. In: Maracz,L. & P. Muysken eds. Configurationality: the typology of asymmetries. Dordrecht: Foris (p. 185-206) HAIDER,H. 1989b. Matching projections. In: A.Cardinaletti & G.Cinque & G.Giusti eds. Constituent Structure. Dordrecht: Foris (p.101-121) HAIDER,H. & RINDLER-SCHJERVE,R. 1987. The parameter of auxiliary selection. Linguis- tics 25: 1029-1055 KOSTER,J. 1978. Locality principles in syntax. Dordrecht:Foris. KOSTER,J. 1987. Domains and Dynasties. Dordrecht: Forsis KRATZER,A. 1984. On deriving differences between German and English. Ms. Technische Universität Berlin PESETZKY,D. 1982. Paths and categories. Unpubl. MIT-Dissertation REINHART,T. 1983. Anaphora and semantic interpretation. London: Croom Helm 15
You can also read