Not my neighbor: Social prejudice and support for democracy
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
Not my neighbor: Social prejudice and support for democracy† Nicholas T. Davis‡ Assistant Professor Department of Political Science University of Alabama Steven V. Miller Associate Professor Department of Political Science Clemson University In theory, Americans like democracy. In practice, this affection is less clear. People like power and are reluctant to cede it, even when they legitimately lose political contests. Why? One explanation involves democracy’s promises: it affords equal access to levers of power via elections, creating natural tensions among groups competing over scare material and psychological resources. Given the central role of race and religion in orienting Americans’ social and political experiences, these tensions are exacerbated when it comes to power-sharing, especially for socially prejudiced citizens. Drawing from an intergroup relations framework, we suspect that white citizens faced with out-group threat may be less inclined to express appreciation for democratic values because democracy supplies access to out- groups who make competing demands on the political system. To study this relationship, this paper explores the concept of neighborliness as an important form of anti-prejudice and proposes several survey experiments to explore the conditions under which social prejudice in neighbor interactions affects citizens’ commitments to democratic values and support for democracy. Key words: democracy, neighbors, neighboring, social prejudice Word count: 8,680 (excluding references) † Paper prepared for presentation at the 2022 annual meeting of the Midwestern Political Science Association, Chicago, Illinois, April 7 – 10, 2022. Parts of this paper were drawn from the working monograph, Not my neighbor: How social prejudice affects support for democracy. ‡ Corresponding author, ntdavis2@ua.edu 0
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 We fall off from the democracy of everyday life when we direct criticism and zealous correction not an individual…but at neighbors as members of a group that to our mind does not belong here. Nancy Rosemblum (2016, 125)1 American democracy is under siege …This reaction spreads by sowing racial fears. Right- wing commentators and activists rail about “replacement theory,” that the growing numbers of people of color threaten to “replace” white America. Rev. Jesse Jackson (2021)2 Ordinary citizens, pundits and scholars alike often lament that there are deep divisions within the American mass public. From automotive preferences (Hetherington and Weiler 2018) to the selection of potential mates (Huber and Malhotra 2016) and to medical decision-making (Crabtree, Holbein, and Monson 2022), political beliefs apparently explain enormous variation in individuals’ behavior and attitudes. In fact, taking the scope of these differences together, the American mass public seems deeply polarized – a state of stark dissimilarity that approaches other sectarian divides like racial, ethnic, and religious conflict (Finkel et al. 2020).3 Certainly, the red-blue, partisan divide in American politics is a chasm both deep and wide (Layman, Carsey, and Horowitz 2006; Iyengar et al. 2019). However, polarization has also come 1 Rosenblum, Nancy L. 2016. Good Neighbors: The Democracy of Everyday Life in America (Princeton: Princeton University Press), p. 125. 2 Jackson, Jesse. “American democracy is under siege.” Chicago Sun Times. Retrieved from: https://chicago.suntimes.com/columnists/2021/12/13/22833301/american-democracy-is-under- siege 3 Despite the seriousness of polarization as a political phenomenon, the lack of introspection regarding this description is as unfortunate as it is common: popularly told, such divisions are observed in far-off backwaters, not the United States. That this country’s singular institutionalized social divide involves race is often lost or flattened in these stories (an irony given the social sorting that lays beneath political polarization). In part, this is probably why the vernacular of “tribe” appears to have taken hold in both lay work and political science research describing mass social-political polarization. Too often, tribe is deployed in implicitly pejorative ways as the baser group unit of lesser civilizations fighting over scarce resources. To be sure, American partisans do not like each other, but greater care is due to the rhetorical frames used by pundits and scientists, alike, in describing such conflict. 1
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 to function as a sanitary, though effective way of removing judgment from descriptions of these divisions. Describing the mass public as polarized both removes the responsibility from any given party for such divisions, and, critically, obscures whether these differences in opinion are normal or appropriate on the substantive merits. The problem, of course, is that not all differences among partisans are a matter of simple aesthetic tastes – differences in support for an insurrection are not equivalent to differences over the appropriate effective tax rate. Thus, while polarization may usefully describe differences in political preferences, the concept often conceals deeper fissures among partisans about basic commitments to the values of democracy. If beliefs about the legitimacy of election rigging (Clayton et al. 2021) and marches in support of white nationalism are any indication (Atkinson 2018), political differences among citizens are so profound that they seem unable to engage in the deliberative processes that are necessary for democratic politics. To this end, the study of the American mass public’s democratic attitudes has come only lately to academic research. To be sure, the study of attitudes relevant to a healthy democracy, involving things like citizens’ commitments to tolerance (Sullivan and Transue 1999), civil liberties (McCloskey and Brill 1983), ideological non-conformity (Cutler and Kaufma 1975), and voting rights (Gronke et al. 2019) have rich histories. But inquiry into commitments to objects like democratic values (e.g. Bright Line Watch,2022) and the democratic order (e.g. Drutman, Diamond, and Goldman 2018; Miller and Davis 2021) – what comparativists might describe as regime support – has only recently begun in earnest in American political science, the result of a visibly and uncommonly undemocratic period that begins with election of Donald Trump to the presidency and continues to worry experts today.4 The findings produced by this research are normatively troubling. Despite rating democracy as a fine system of governance, supporting it above alternatives, and recognizing norm violations (Davis, Gaddie, and Goidel, forthcoming), a non-trivial proportion of the mass public exhibits soft authoritarian commitments (Drutman, Diamond, and Goldman 2018) and a willingness to renege on longstanding norms when it is politically expedient (Graham and Svolik 2020; Simonovits, McCoy,and Littvay 2021; Frederiksen 2022). Citizens persuaded by lies about “the big steal” and have lost confidence in elections after the 2020 presidential election (Clayton et 4 This is not to oversell the integrity of American democracy prior to this point. The United States wallowed in partial democracy until the passage of the 1965 Voting Rights Act, and, even then, struggled to implement the civil integration promised in the Civil Rights Act of 1964 for the next several decades without the threat of injunction. The democratic deficits in the interim – the gap between the promises of democracy and the production of democratic goods – are severe and still felt today. Former president Donald Trump was the fulmination of these failures, but it is important to contextualize that presidency against deeper democratic failures. For their part, academic political science has been (frustratingly) slow to draw those connections. 2
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 al. 2021) – attitudes that are not “just” expressive responding but apparently genuine (Graham and Yair, n.d.). Within this growing body of research, the finding that anti-democratic attitudes break somewhat cleanly along partisan lines seemingly dovetails with the broader polarization research – Democrats are (generally) more supportive of democratic norms than Republicans (Bright Line Watch, 2022; Cagle and Davis 2022), even as the pressures of the two-party system mean that all partisans will hold their noses and cast votes for norm-breaking politicians (Graham and Svolik 2020; Simonovits, McCoy,and Littvay 2021). The result is that differences in such attitudes are treated as yet one more piece of evidence that American partisans live in two separate realities. The problem with this depiction, of course, is that the rhetorical framing involved in “polarization” assumes that there are two legitimate perspectives underlying this disconnect. That some citizens give pro-democratic responses to survey instruments and others authoritarian or violent ones (Kalmoe and Mason, 2022), however, is not evidence of polarization. It is instead evidence of a seismic shift in commitments to what scholars call the basic “rules of the game”; evidence that the democratic consensus is cracking apart at the seams. Why? Why is it that these partisan differences manifest in different support for democratic values? What else explains how individuals regard democracy? What ideational material undergirds different conclusions about the promises of democracy? Recent research suggests that core political values – focal points that help people understand the complex political environment (Schwartz, Caprara, and Vecchione 2010; Goren, Smith, and Motta 2020) – have more or less sorted alongside other social and political identities (Ciuk 2022). Early democratic consensus grounded in a political culture of Lockean liberalism, which emphasized freedom and egalitarianism, occurred within a narrow social framework. That is, democratic politics was historically an environment where democratic values and participation were reserved for a monolithic racial block – white men. While tensions within modern American political culture largely still center on equality and individualism (McCloskey and Zaller 1984; Davis, Gaddie and Goidel forthcoming), the opening of herrenvolk democracy to others via enfranchisement in the mid-20th Century corresponds to the beginning of a social sorting that involves the grafting of religious, racial, and ethnic identities onto political ideology (Mason 2018; Davis 2018). One consequence of this development involves drawing sharp lines involving legitimacy and access to the polity on the basis of race, thereby creating dissensus not just in core political values, but democratic ones, as well. However, while the racial attitudes of white Americans shape democratic preferences (Miller and Davis 2021), the role of religion – or more specifically, evangelicalism – cannot be 3
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 ignored. The story of race lynching, Jim Crow, the subsequent fight against integration after the Civil Rights Act cannot be fully understood without situating institutionalized racism as a piece of religious expression (Ehrenhaus and Owen 2004). More recently, evangelical discourse after September 11, 2001 displays an intense, anti-democratic antagonism against Muslims, while the growth of Christian nationalism in the interim is a “threat to American democracy” (Gorksi and Perry 2022).5 In many respects, then, prejudice is the plumbline that orients American politics (Roberts and Rizzo 2021). What’s missing from this research on democratic values, however, is a more thorough examination of how, much less when social prejudice motivates white Americans to support or undercut the principles of democracy. In this paper, we begin by sketching out the relationship between social prejudice, which we define broadly as exclusionary attitudes toward racial, ethnic, or religious out-groups, and democracy. With a particular emphasis on Rosenblum’s (2016) concept of neighborliness as a form of anti-prejudice – a key relational quality linked to pluralism that conveys comfortability with letting “others” into social and sacred spaces – we propose several survey experiments that explore how the pressures of (neighborly) diversity shape the conditions under which citizens profess more (and less) support for democracy. The psychology of social prejudice Definitions of (social) prejudice are numerous for a concept that seems intuitive. In his foundational, midcentury work, social psychologist Gordon Allport described prejudice in relatively simple terms, as “an antipathy based upon a faulty and inflexible generalization. It may be felt or expressed. It may be directed toward a group as a whole or toward an individual because he is a member of that group” (Allport 1954, 10). In Prejudice and Racism, Jones (1972, 61) takes a similarly broad view, defining prejudice as “an unjustified negative attitude towards an individual based solely on that individual’s membership in a group.” But while these feelings involve any “members of socially defined groups” (Stephan 1983, 417), they often involve a person belonging to a “minority group” (Levin and Levin 1982, 66). Such views are not accidental nor merely fleeting but encompass a “display of hostile or discriminatory behavior towards members of a group on account of their membership in that group” (Brown 1995, 8). 5 A quote taken directly from their book, The Flag and the Cross: White Christian Nationalism and the threat to American Democracy. 4
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Despite competing but often complimentary definitions of social prejudice, there is a great deal of agreement that prejudice is not ephemeral, but a concrete attitude.6 In other words, prejudice may dwell within the unseen lands of the human psyche, but it can nevertheless be observed and, critically, measured.7 Thus, the result is a general tendency to describe prejudice as the “affective component of intergroup relations” (Brewer and Kramer 1985). If prejudice involves negative reactions to persons belonging to (minority) social groups, then such attitudes are bad, according to Allport 1954, 7), because they are faulty or incorrect – without “sufficient warrant.” Others describe it in plainer terms. Milner (1975, 9) describes prejudice as an “unjust” attitude, while Rose (1951, 5) proposes that it “justifies discrimination.” In each of these cases, prejudice is problematic because it violates normative ideals involving reciprocity. If there are social standards that people ought to follow but don’t for reasons involving immutable features or stereotypes, then violating these obligations is fundamentally wrong (Harding et al. 1969). People may hold prejudices for various reasons, but, across the various intergroup explanations of social behavior, group salience and categorization play important roles. Prejudice occurs when people are both sensitive to their own identities (e.g. Simon 2008) and when they are able to categorize others into attendant in- or out-groups (e.g. Turner et al. 1987). In turn, the motivations behind these processes are often split into different explanations involving both material and psychological considerations (e.g. Bobo 1983). Realistic interest approaches suggest that tangible gains and losses motivate whether individuals engage in discrimination (Esses et al. 2005), while symbolic frameworks convey that prejudice is motivated by positive distinctiveness (Kinder and Sears 1981) – that is, people hold their in-group in high emotional regard, often at the expense of an out-group (a process that involves out-group derogation; for a brief, but helpful review of these dynamics in political science research, see: Huddy and Bankert [2017]). While the intergroup relations literature is prodigious and social-psychological theories about the motivations of discrimination numerous, our operating approach casts a wide net with 6 Milner (1981, 112) famously noted that, in regards to defining prejudice, “there are almost as many definitions of the term as writers who employ it.” This summary isn’t wrong, but there is still much overlap regarding operating definitions of it. 7 In part, the hidden nature of prejudice and the demands of polite society are why scholars have shown such interest in “implicit” prejudice (sometimes called “unconscious bias”). For a discussion about why implicit prejudice is a thorny concept mired in theoretical debate and practical relevance, see: Mitchell, Gregory, and Philip E. Tetlock. 2017. “Popularity as a poor proxy for utility: The case of implicit prejudice.” In Lilienfeld, Scott O. and Irwin D. Waldman (Eds.), Psychological science under scrutiny: Recent challenges and proposed solutions, 164- 195. 5
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 regards to the general form that social prejudice takes.8 Social prejudice involves exclusionary and discriminatory attitudes toward others and functions as a parent construct under which racial, ethnic, and religious discrimination fit. Each respective “type” of prejudice draws from similar wells within the intergroup conflict literature involving threat. For example, whites’ racism toward Blacks can occur when they perceive threats to their self-image, values and beliefs, or resources (Riek, Mania, and Gaertner 2006). Likewise, nativism is grounded in the conflict between “native” citizens and outsiders (Larsen et al. 2009; Davis et al. 2019; ).9 When non- natives are perceived to threaten predominating cultural norms or economic wellbeing, prejudice results (Zárate et al. 2004). Finally, while it is possible that “love they neighbor” jeremiads might increase sympathy for religious out-groups, “…religious intergroup relations are no different from any other form of intergroup relation” (Jackson and Hunsberger 1999) – including the attendant prejudice that surfaces when traditional religious norms are threatened by newly salient or different religious traditions that involve racial or ethnic outgroups (e.g. Muslims in the United States after September 11, 2001). These social prejudices present several problems for democracy. If living in a democratic community is possible because of a shared commitment to pluralism – a set of social conditions in which a diversity of views is permitted, if not encouraged – then social prejudice makes it difficult to engage in peaceful deliberation, much less inclusion. Those biases circumvent the creed that access to levers of power should ignore characteristics like race or religion. Worse, they violate the tenets of neighborliness, which are core to a healthy democratic peace (Rosenblum 2016) – an idea we take up momentarily. Over the last several decades, the measurement of prejudice has generated enormous debate about the structure and contours of white Americans’ attitudes toward out-groups (e.g. Kinder and Sears 1981; Sniderman et al. 1991; Sidanius, Pratto, and Bobo 1996; Bobo 1999; DeSante and Smith 2020; Carney and Enos n.d.). From symbolic (Kinder and Sears 1981; Kinder and Sanders 1996) and modern racism (McConahay 1986) to laissez-faire (Bobo, Kluegel, and Smith 1997) and aversive racism (Gaertner and Dovidio 1986), scholars have devoted significant time and effort to uncovering the shape and motivations of Americans’ racial views (see also: 8 Despite social psychological frameworks “competing” against each other to “best” describe the “true” motivations for why people display prejudice, a generous view of these literatures suggests that different theories have strengths and weaknesses. For our purposes, we believe that symbolic and material threat contribute to why some white Americans display anti-democratic tendencies. 9 “Native” is a somewhat ironic term in this research agenda in that it doesn’t really involve “first peoples” who might have had an original claim to a region, but, instead, represents a sort of (racialized) quasi-citizen concept. To be native in this framework is to be someone who has a formal claim of belonging; in contrast, non-natives are foreign or, more acrimoniously, alien. 6
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 DeSante and Smith [2020] and Davis and Wilson’s [2021] recent work in political science). Despite being an admirable goal, this research agenda is commonly frustrated by disciplinary silos, terminology, motivations, and goals.10 Prejudice can seemingly be explained by both symbolic and material demands, may be inherently logical or “principled,” and, perhaps not even about race at all (e.g. Lerner 1980). We agree that the psychometric properties of attitudes are important and that the empirical properties of them should guide theorizing both their functions and the conclusions drawn about them.11 That said, our approach here is guided by a different theoretical goal. Our interest is not simply, say, racism or religious discrimination, particularly, but a broader form of social prejudice involved in the concept of neighborliness (or lack thereof) – whether people willingly accept or reject living next to someone from a racial, ethnic, or religious out-group. In a vacuum, there are few reasons why someone should willingly exclude someone from a particular religious or racial group from their immediate social space. There are certainly rational reasons of solidarity involved in wanting to live next to one’s kin. And social structures may conspire to sort and reproduce racial homophily (Sampson and Sharkey 2008). But, at the individual-level, attitudes involving the exclusion of out-group neighbors on the basis of immutable characteristics like the color of one’s skin or on other social group memberships like religion, clearly constitute a thorny form of social prejudice.12 In our view, thinking about these attitudes as a form of social prejudice not only also sidestep some of the controversy regarding the peculiarities of longstanding measurement protocols of various forms of, say, racial bias, but has clear application to democracy. Not my neighbor – How neighborly exclusion undercuts democratic support To sketch out a theory for how the rejection of neighborly goodwill constitutes a disturbing form of social prejudice and, critically, motivates a rebuke of democracy, we begin with a brief discussion of the relationship between community – the social dimension of neighborhood environments – and democracy. Friedland (2001, 358) writes plainly that “For democracy to 10 Davis and Wilson’s (2021) book on racial resentment carefully reviews these debates and controversies and their implications for the study of prejudice in American politics. It is an uncommonly lucid account of the differences involved in measuring racism across political science and social psychology literatures. 11 Although we would humbly add that the logic of ordinary experience sometimes seems strangely foreign to the econometric analysis favored by social scientists, who seem determined to construe prejudice as uniquely complicated and reducible to a simply keystroke (see: Sen and Wasow’s [2016] excellent work on this point). 12 In some sense, it is kin to the classic resistance toward integration. 7
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 work, community is necessary.” Democracy is not just a system in which election are held (e.g. Przeworski 1991), but requires, on some level, a democratic culture that both values deliberative debate and promotes participation (Rosenblum 2016). Such conditions are never totally fulfilled, which lends such features an idealistic quality. Such “strong” views of democracy (Dewey 1928; Habermas 1962/1989) probably fail on the merits of the evidence that citizens are often too busy to vote, rarely engage in meaningful exchange, and know only a modest deal about the workings of politics. But the unfulfillment of these demands is less important than the underlying cultural commitments to live out such democratic values. In other words the failure of democratic community does not mute aspirations to achieve it. Despite this view of community as the ethereal social dimension to neighbor interactions, communities are also physical. While it is true that the “tightly bounded, well-integrated community that we associate with the rural village, the city neighborhood, and even the suburb no longer correspond to a social structure characterized by more complex patterns of mobility and migration” (Friedland 2001, 364), housed people nevertheless live somewhere. And despite economic, cultural, and technological upheaval (Castells 1996), the physical community is where much of citizens’ social experiences and, by extension, experiences with democracy unfold. Sometimes, the experiences in community are positive, like the shopkeeper looking out for a child on her way home from the bus stop. But other times community interactions are hostile, such as when residents slow integration or block outsiders from settling. In that case, discrimination often prevents individuals from entering in and enjoying the benefits of community; it prevents others from entering into sacred social spaces.13 When communities exclude others based on categorical features like race, ethnicity, or religion, the disregard for commitments to democratic values are revealed. Social prejudice, then, threatens the very fabric of what political theorist Nancy Rosenblum (2016) labels “the democracy of everyday life.” Within communities, the most common or routine interactions occur between neighbors. Of course, this is not to say that all persons in a community are immediate neighbors. That idea is simultaneously too broad and too restrictive. Neighbors are near to us, but the exact distance where one transitions from acquaintance to neighbor is hard to explicitly define. “Neighbors are not just people living nearby,” writes Rosemblum (2016, 2), but are, instead “our environment.” 13 The fact that so many Americans are stationary only serves to reinforce these tendencies – the percentage of people who have changed residences in the 2020 was the lowest it has been since the Census began tracking that information (about 8%; Fry, Richard and D’Vera Cohn. 2021. “In 2020, fewer Americans moved, exodus from cities slowed.” Pew Research Center. Retrieved from: https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2021/12/16/in-2020-fewer-americans-moved- exodus-from-cities-slowed/. 8
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 This definition tends to lend “neighbor” an amorphous quality, but it is enough to simply note that neighbors are proximate relationships that involve both “mutual hospitality” and “a selective invitation to mind one another’s business” (3). The practice of neighborliness has a moral aspect and guides one’s expectations and daily encounters with others. In other words, being a “good neighbor” is both a norm and a practice.14 In several important aspects, neighborliness also functions as a “form of democratic excellence” (Rosenblum 2016, 7). Despite the novelist’s tendency to depict neighborliness as a sentimental expression, its practice is deeply emblematic of the demands of democracy.15 Neighbors give and take offense, yet abide by mutual norms that sustain their wellbeing. If “the stuff of a civilization consists largely of its substantive norms” (Ellickson 1991, xxi), then neighborliness softens the competitive, individualistic ethos that edges of the individualism that accompanies American democracy. No man is an island. Not only does neighborliness permit the sort of (para)social fraternization that is conducive to pluralism, but it counterbalances freedom in the extreme. According to Rosenblum’s (2016) work, there are several elements that comprise neighborliness, or the “democracy of everyday life” – the form of social exchange necessary to successfully build a democratic culture. Chief among this is the governing normative commitment to reciprocity, which encourages engaging with people whose categorical attributes differ from their own. Reciprocity ignores “the rules of social hierarchy, rank, class, kinship, or sectarianism” that permeate other relationships. To be a good neighbor is to simply return, in kind, the sort of treatment that sustains peaceable interactions; it is, in some sense, a form of anti- prejudice. 14 Rosenblum describes the concept of “good neighbor” as a regulatory ideal, an idea that riffs on Foucault’s notion of something that functions as a norm but is part of a regulatory practice that controls. 15 It is worth noting, however, that neighborliness is not citizenship. Rosenblum (2016) acknowledges the tendency to flatten neighborliness as an outgrowth of good citizenship, to assume that the former is a quality expressed by the latter. But this is wrong on some level. Neighborliness requires more and less than citizenship. It is not governed by political institutions or legal codes. And citizenship, which implies being bound to the rules of the game may put neighborliness in jeopardy. It may be the case that a good neighbor permits activities that actually contravene the qualities of being a good citizen. A good citizen, for example, might be “required” to report the moonshine still operating on her neighbor’s back acreage or an undocumented worker living next door. Neither action may exhibit neighborliness. In our framework, citizenship is effectively endogenous to “support for democracy”; it is, quite literally, an expression of democratic values, and linking good citizenship to it feels like selecting on the dependent variable, as it were. 9
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 This commitment is worked out in several cases, like when neighbors “live and let live.” The ideal of live and let live means that there may be occasions where people exhibit self- discipline and allow differences or slights to occur without consequence because they are interested in the preservation of a status quo. But when neighbors recognize behavior or outcomes that cannot stand because they are indecent or unbecoming, they may display restraint or speak out. Both incorporate a form of deliberate self-governance that is grounded in the commitment to great others as anyone would like to be treated. Neighborliness fails when these commitments are replaced by exclusion and harm, and they can be observed in circumstances where community threats are described using the language of social prejudice. From the panics over Chinese immigrants looking for work in the 19th Century, to panics over dangerous racialized “no-go” zones, and to Islamophobia linking faith to terrorism, politicians often connect community, neighbors, and social prejudice when they use discriminatory rhetoric to talk about the pressing threat of outsiders. “Why do we want all these people from ‘shithole countries’ coming here?” former president Donald Trump remarked in 2018. In his view, those people were “invading” the country, threatening American communities.16 This stereotyping fixates on the ascriptive characteristics of the immigrant, which functions as a rebuke to neighborliness and, critically, “builds walls” – here both literally and metaphorically. Instead of a higher road marked by a commitment to neighborliness, “[t]here is no learning. No accommodation. No appreciation of shared reality. No imagination or empathy” (Rosenblum 2016, 126). If neighboring is the foundation of social cohesion (Forrest and Kearns 2001), then such social prejudice is the antithesis of it.17 These ideas about the importance of neighborliness to democracy bring us to the following set of expectations. Despite their peculiarities, group conflict theory cuts across racial, ethnic, and religious forms of prejudice. Whether nativism, religious discrimination, or racism, prejudice involves categorizing people into groups via harmful stereotypes that are then essentialized. That is, group characteristics are imputed upon individuals when making judgments. When that process occurs, group features are assigned to individuals in ways that are 16 Dawsey, Josh. January 12, 2018. “Trump derides protections for immigrants from ‘shithole’ countries.” The Washington Post. Retrieved from: https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/trump-attacks-protections-for-immigrants-from- shithole-countries-in-oval-office-meeting/2018/01/11/bfc0725c-f711-11e7-91af- 31ac729add94_story.html. 17 This argument is not only theoretical. Empirically, the practice of good neighbor – “neighboring” – is associated with several positive individual level outcomes, like sense of belonging and security (Henning and Lieberg 1996), and collective ones, like social capital (Putnam 2000) and community integration (Wu 2016). 10
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 unfair and unjust; convenient distinctions transition from being descriptive to prescriptive (c.f. Roberts and Rizzo 2021). In the case of (some) white Americans, “whiteness” can function as a powerful form of social identity, which involves the incorporation of a group membership into the self-concept (Jardina 2019). Drawing from social identity theory (Turner et al. 1987), this process involves viewing an identity group’s goals as central to the psychological wellbeing of the individual – a feeling of solidarity with the plight of one’s group members. When individuals exhibit racist, xenophobic, or religiously discriminatory beliefs, they construct distinctions between in- and out- group members. They demarcate who is the acceptable member of a community and who is the apostate. This process strips away the neighborliness that underwrites democratic exchange by placing a group’s perceived wellbeing ahead of the wellbeing of the larger community. To be a neighbor is to live in community. A neighbor cuts across these group boundaries in a way that allows people to live shoulder to shoulder with others. Living in community requires honoring the values that make democracy possible; rejecting neighbors on the basis of ascriptive features, in contrast, makes a mockery of democratic culture.18 In this story, then, actively rejecting neighbors who look or speak differently or practice different religions serves as a form of social prejudice.19 Despite some research that argues that the compositional nature of neighborhoods works similarly regardless of one’s racial group – that is, whites and blacks express reluctance to live in diverse neighborhoods because they are more likely to be poorer, less safe, and contain worse schools (Harris 2001) – our argument sidesteps those findings because it involves imaging immediate neighbors not the more global community.20 This difference is crucial. To exclude someone as a direct neighbor invokes a personal contrast different from imaging embedding oneself in a fundamentally different neighborhood full of the attendant, albeit stereotypical issues that might be associated with such places.21 Our argument isn’t strictly about place, per se, but people. And, 18 It is important not to confuse what people do with who people are. It is entirely rational for someone to say “I do not wish to live next to a murderer.” But this is qualitatively different from saying “I do not wish to live next to someone who speaks a different language.” And despite the allure of solidarity – i.e. wanting to live next to someone who looks or thinks like you do – rejecting potential neighbors on account of immutable features is a distinct form of social prejudice – the very logic that justified state-sponsored segregation in the United States. 19 For an early version of this argument see Miller and Davis (2021). 20 That argument also fails to account for the dramatic growth and self-segregation of exurbs by white Americans (e.g. Lichter, Parisi Taquino 2015). 21 However, again, we would be remiss not to acknowledge that there is a persistent finding that white Americans are very reluctant to live in neighborhoods where they are the minority (e.g. Zubrinsky and Bobo 1996). And while we’ve noted that some research finds these preferences cut 11
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 if democracy extends access and power to all people regardless of race or creed – which includes those persons who may be undesirable as neighbors – then it may be a threatening system of governance for the socially-prejudiced because it legitimizes “those people” as equals. Studying the relationship among neighborliness, social prejudice, and support for democracy Our past (and ongoing) research illustrates that social prejudice – whether defined via traditional measures of “negative” attitudes toward racial, ethnic, and religious outgroups or the rejection of such individuals as neighbors – is linked to less support for democracy. What is less clear is whether out-group threat and anti-neighborliness causally affect democratic attitudes. In what follows, we present materials for three survey experiments that attempt to triangulate how anti- neighborliness affects democratic values and support. Study 1 – Neighbor diversity and democratic attitudes Neighborhoods are where the values of neighborliness are stress-tested. They are also where democratic values are worked out in an intimate manner; local communities are the frontlines of democracy, supplying opportunities for representation (e.g. serving on local school boards) and participation (e.g. voting on referenda, tax abatements, and the like) for ordinary citizens within a context that “matters” deeply to them (community cite). This setting, then, supplies fertile ground to test the relationship of different forms of out-group threat on democratic attitudes. The trouble with using “neighborhoods” as a level of abstraction is that neighborhoods involve an almost corporeal quality – they can be large or small; they can be literal or imaginary (Rosenblum 2016 + cite). In this study, we randomly assign subjects to one of two configurations of streets to imagine living on – their immediate “neighborhood.”22 Recall that our argument about social prejudice is that it functions as a diffuse form of bias that encompasses more than “just” racism or nativism. It is additive, and it is difficult to measure in an instrumental fashion across racial groups, recent research finds that “white flight” is persistent and that whites generally give socially desirable responses about living in diverse neighborhoods (Kye and Halpern-Manners 2019). Thus, neighborhood preferences may be as politically consequential to democratic attitudes as neighbor preferences – something we return to in Study 1. 22 Inadvertently and, to some degree, unavoidably, this stylized treatment privileges a suburban view of neighborhood / community. Not everyone lives on a quarter acre with a white picket fence; in fact, many times direct neighbors are those people who live down the hall or in the connecting townhome. No treatment is perfect, and we recognize this as a limitation of this thought exercise. Study 2 attempts to triangulate this problem by asking subjects to focus on their next-door neighbor, allowing “next-door” to vary in the mind of the respondent. 12
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 where one can calculate, for example, subtle differences in antiblack vs. anti-Muslim affect. Thus, our choice of treatments is a “bundled” one. Subjects are not asked to participate in a conjoint task, where we can seemingly pull out the marginal effect of the share of Hispanics living in a neighborhood relative the share of Black residents, as if this were a practical way of thinking about how these biases work (Sen and Wasow 2016). Instead, we attempt to provide some realistic fidelity to this task by simply describing two scenarios: a “low” (in-group) and “high” diversity (out-group) setting. White subjects being by taking a short pre-test questionnaire that includes a task asking them to identify people with whom they would not want as neighbors (see Table 1 for questionnaire). Based on responses to this question, we then block randomize individuals by social prejudice to one of three conditions: (1) placebo control, (2) high diversity neighbors, or (3) low diversity neighbors.23 Individuals in the latter two conditions are then asked to read the following prompt. Now, we would like you to imagine living in a neighborhood with decent schools, a fair cost of living, and where access to restaurants and other outdoor activities like parks and a community pool are only a short drive away. [The neighbors on your street are a diverse group from different racial and religious backgrounds. / The neighbors on your street might look a lot like you.] To help you imagine yourself in this place, we’ll show you a few pictures of some of the people who might live on your street. Afterwards, we’ll ask you to rate how comfortable you’d be moving to this neighborhood and conclude with a few more unrelated questions. Figures 1 and 2 portray the images associated with the high and low diversity treatments, respectively. Each image in Figure 1 roughly corresponds to a mirror image in Figure 2. For example, a smiling Muslim couple (Figure 1) can be juxtaposed against a smiling white couple (Figure 2); likewise, an older Hispanic man in Figure 1 has a similar white counterpart in Figure 2. After viewing the set of images, we ask subjects to convey on a scale of 1 to 10 how comfortable they would be moving in to a house on this street.24 Then, they answer several questions meant to capture their support for democracy. 23 Block randomization by social prejudice is necessary to ensure that we evenly spread those who exhibit social prejudice out among the conditions. Past research suggests that anywhere between 15 and 20 percent of respondents give a “social prejudice” response to the neighbor preferences battery (see Table 1), so it is necessary to ensure that we do not, by random chance, isolate such respondents in any one condition. 24 The images were chosen strategically and pulled from Google images. Given the large literature regarding facial attractiveness (see: Little 2021 for a review), we attempted to balance the photos so as to not stack the deck visually – in other words, we avoided “threatening” facial cues (frowns, displeasure) and used only stock photography that did not give off contextual background cues (urban or suburban settings). 13
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Given pressures of out-group threat, we would expect individuals in the high-diversity condition to report less positive dispositions toward democracy. In contrast, individuals in the low-diversity condition should report higher ratings of support for democracy. We also compare outcomes from both groups against a placebo control to assess how priming a neighborhood’s demographic composition shapes democratic views compared to latent democratic support. Because we collect the neighbor preferences battery, we also plan to explore whether there are heterogenous treatment effects among the socially prejudiced. We would expect that persons who supplied a anti-neighborly responses to the battery would be more likely to be negatively affected by the “high diversity” condition relative other subjects. These people should convey especially negative evaluations of democracy / commitments to democratic values. 14
Figure 1. Treatment images for street with “high diversity” 15
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Figure 2. Treatment images for street with “low diversity” 16
Table 1. Selected instruments from Study 1 questionnaire Pre-test Neighbor preferences On the list below are different people who you might encounter in your neighborhood. Please select those persons on the list who you would NOT want as your next-door neighbor. Drug addict People of a different race Lawyer Immigrant People who practice a different religion Unmarried couples living together People who speak a different language A heavy drinker Loud partiers A previously-convicted non-violent felon Post-test Manipulation check Having thought about this neighborhood, how comfortable would you be living on a street with these people? (1) very uncomfortable…(10) very comfortable Democratic values / support Please convey which of the following two ideas comes closer to how you think about voting: (1) Voting is a right or (2) voting is a privilege. Do you strongly agree (1), agree (2), neither agree nor disagree (3), disagree (4), or strongly disagree (5) with the following statements? People should be required to demonstrate civic knowledge before voting. Military officials would make better government leaders than elected officials. Note: Full survey includes the usual suspects regarding sociodemographic information. 17
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Study 2 – Priming the “other” If Study 1 attempts to prime the neighborhood context, Study 2 involves priming the qualities of the next-door neighbor. This context is the most intimate neighborly relationship by virtue of proximity. The next-door neighbor may be the tenet to your left, the folks who live in the detached house next to yours, or the people who stay on the property adjacent to your acreage. Regardless of the actual physical proximity, however, there is intimacy in the idea of “next-door neighbor.” This is the person most proximate to the everyday mundanity of one’s life. Study 2 involves a simple racial cue priming experiment. Subjects take a brief pre-test and are then told that they’ll be randomly assigned to view a profile of someone who will be moving in next door. The prompt’s text reads: Now, imagine that tomorrow you are getting a new next-door neighbor. You’ll be randomly assigned a profile of this new neighbor. Please read their brief biography carefully. After, you’ll be asked a question about how comfortable you’d be with this person as your next-door neighbor. Subjects are then given the exact same biographical sketch across conditions; the only difference involved the visual cue (race) of the figure in each vignette, along with the phrase used to describe the potential new neighbor. The vignettes are available in Figure 2. Each image is cropped to the same dimensions, includes the same white background, and depicts an unsmiling, younger-middle-aged man. Per Lucas et al. (2011), the images exhibit rough parity in attractiveness and facial structure. Conditions 1 – 3 correspond to the neighbor preferences battery insofar as they contain persons who belong to a different race, are an immigrant, or may speak a different language. As such, we have no concrete expectations about differences in the positivity of democratic attitudes for subjects randomly assigned to these groups. However, subjects in those three conditions should be, on balance, more negative in their support for democracy relative white subjects assigned to condition 4, which depicts a traditional white man. Again, we test for heterogenous treatment effects by exploring whether persons who exhibit social prejudice are more likely to supply weaker commitments to democracy than those who do not exhibit such bias. In Study 2, we again collect pre-test information about subjects’ neighbor preferences along with demographic data. Then, after reading the vignette of their new, hypothetical next- door neighbor, we collect subjects’ views about whether this person would be suitable to them. Finally, we conclude with a series of questions that tap into participants’ support for democratic values. 18
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Figure 2. Study 2 treatments and vignettes. (1) African American (3) Muslim Jerome Jones is single, African American man in Adeel Shah is a single Muslim man in his late his late 30s. He works as an administrative 30s. He works as an administrative services services manager at a local business and has a manager at a local business and has a bachelor’s bachelor’s degree in accounting from a small degree in accounting from a small public public university. He is unmarried, but has a university. He is unmarried, but has a young young child who will occasionally stay with him child who will occasionally stay with him every every other weekend. other weekend. (2) Immigrant (Hispanic) (4) White Miguel Hernandez is a single man in his late 30s Sam Jones is a single Caucasian man in his late who recently immigrated to the United States. 30s. He works as an administrative services He works as an administrative services manager manager at a local business and has a bachelor’s at a local business and has a bachelor’s degree in degree in accounting from a small public accounting from a small public university. He is university. He is unmarried, but has a young unmarried, but has a young child who will child who will occasionally stay with him every occasionally stay with him every other weekend. other weekend. Notes: Stimuli taken from Lucas, Heather D., Joan Y. Chiao, and Ken A. Paller. 2011. “Why some faces won’t be remembered: Brain potentials illuminate successful versus unsuccessful encoding for same-race and other-race faces. 19
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Table 2. Selected instruments from Study 1 questionnaire Pre-test Neighbor preferences On the list below are different people who you might encounter in your neighborhood. Please select those persons on the list who you would NOT want as your next-door neighbor. Drug addict People of a different race Lawyer Immigrant People who practice a different religion Unmarried couples living together People who speak a different language A heavy drinker Loud partiers A previously-convicted non-violent felon Post-test Manipulation check Would you like or not like this person to be your new next-door neighbor? (1) would not want as next-door neighbor…(10) would want as next-door neighbor Democratic values / support Please convey which of the following two ideas comes closer to how you think about voting: (1) Voting is a right or (2) voting is a privilege. Do you strongly agree (1), agree (2), neither agree nor disagree (3), disagree (4), or strongly disagree (5) with the following statements? People should be required to demonstrate civic knowledge before voting. Military officials would make better government leaders than elected officials. Please indicated how important you think the following features are to democracy. 1 (not important…10 (important) Government officials are appropriately punished for misconduct. Government agencies are not used to monitor, attack, or punish political opponents. Government does not interfere with journalists or news organizations Government protects individuals’ right to engage in unpopular speech or expression All adult citizens have equal opportunity to vote The geographic boundaries of electoral districts do not systematically advantage any particular political party Elected officials seek compromise with political opponents Government protects individuals’ right to engage in peaceful protest The law is enforced equally for all persons Incumbent politicians who lose elections publicly concede defeat 20
Not my neighbor Davis and Miller, MPSA 2022 Study 3 – Neighbors and (dis)similarity Study 3 builds on the simple racial cues supplied to subjects in studies 1 and 2. In this experimental design, we press into the ideas of similarity and dissimilarity to test whether subjects can be primed out of their biases, by emphasizing unity, or pushed further into anti- neighborliness, by imaging dissimilarities. To accomplish this, we use a 2x2 design that varies both group status and the characteristics we ask subjects to focus on. In each condition, we tell subjects to imagine a next-door neighbor and direct them to write a few short comments about this person. In the first two conditions, subjects are asked to imagine a next-door neighbor who looks like them. The key differences is whether we ask them to focus on their perceived similarities (condition 1) or differences (condition 2). In the third and fourth groups, we ask subjects to imagine a next-door neighbor who looks different from them on the basis of race or religious preferences. Again, we ask subjects to either imagine differences (condition 3) or similarities (condition 4) they share with these out-group neighbors. Finally, condition five (control) functions as a true baseline against which to compare the in- and out-group neighbor conditions. Here, subjects simply take the pre- and post-test questionnaire (the same instrument depicted in Table 1). The full text of the different prompts is available in Table 2. Again, we conclude the experiment by asking subjects some questions about their attitudes toward democracy. Our expectations are simple. We suspect that support for democracy should be highest in the in-group similarity condition (low threat) and lowest in the out-group dissimilarity condition (high threat). The other two conditions supply different ways of nibbling around the edges of how group dynamics operate. If dissimilarity is negative – and negative information is threatening or weights more heavily on the brain (Ito et al. 1998) – then perhaps there would be no differences in the in- and out-group dissimilarity conditions. But, given that we’ve asked subjects to ruminate on racial, ethnic, or religious characteristics of the imaginary neighbor, that contrast allows us to test whether any neighborly dissimilarity suppresses democratic support or if it is specific to conditions where an out-group member is present. Study 3 uses the study 1 questionnaire to collect participants’ views about potential neighbors and support for democracy. In addition, because the manipulation is partially a writing task, we plan to analyze the text to in each group to assess substance and polarity. We would expect that the most negative reflections about the imaginary neighbor will occur in the out-group dissimilarity condition. 21
Table 2. Treatment vignettes for Study 2 Condition 1: In-group differences Condition 2: In-group similarities Condition 3: Out-group differences Condition 4: Out-group similarities Next, we’d like you to spend a few Next, we’d like you to spend a few Next, we’d like you to spend a few Next, we’d like you to spend a few moments thinking about your moments thinking about your moments thinking about your moments thinking about your neighborhood. Imagine that the house neighborhood. Imagine that the house neighborhood. Imagine that the house neighborhood. Imagine that the house or apartment next door is recently or apartment next door is recently or apartment next door is recently or apartment next door is recently vacant. Tomorrow new neighbors are vacant. Tomorrow new neighbors are vacant. Tomorrow new neighbors are vacant. Tomorrow new neighbors are moving in, and they are pretty similar moving in, and they are pretty similar moving in, and they are a bit different moving in, and they are a bit different to you. Maybe you speak the same to you. Maybe you speak the same from you. Maybe their first language from you. Maybe their first language language, work in similar places, and language, work in similar places, and isn’t English, they belong to a isn’t English, they belong to a go to the same community events or go to the same community events or different racial group, and they different racial group, and they church. Try to picture these neighbors church. Try to picture these neighbors practice a different religion. Try to practice a different religion. Try to in your mind. in your mind. picture these neighbors in your mind. picture these neighbors in your mind. Now, we’d like you to write a Now, we’d like you to write a Now, we’d like you to write a Now, we’d like you to write a sentence or two about the potential sentence or two about the potential sentence or two about the potential sentence or two about the potential differences that you could imagine commonalities between you and these differences that you could imagine commonalities between you and these would come between you and these neighbors. What are some benefits would come between you and these neighbors. What are some benefits neighbors. What are some difficulties that you imagine might arise from neighbors. What are some difficulties that you imagine might arise from that you imagine might arise from having these folks as your as your that you imagine might arise from having these folks as your as your having these folks as your as your neighbors? Despite your differences, having these folks as your as your neighbors? Despite your differences, neighbors? What complications or what advantages or benefits might neighbors? What complications or what advantages or benefits might misunderstandings might arise arise from having these new misunderstandings might arise from arise from having these new despite your similarities? neighbors? these neighbors being different from neighbors? you? Notes: The full experimental matrix is a 2 (group) x 2 (similarity) design. In addition to the four treatments listed here, a fifth placebo condition serves as a true baseline to gauge democratic opinions. 22
You can also read