Theory of Mind in Children with Cerebral Palsy and Severe Speech Impairment
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
Theory of Mind in Children with Cerebral Palsy and Severe Speech Impairment Kerstin W. Falkman, Annika Dahlgren Sandberg and Erland Hjelmquist Department of Psychology, Göteborg University, Sweden Falkman, K. W., Dahlgren Sandberg, A., & Hjelmquist, E., Theory of Mind in Children with Cerebral Palsy and Severe Speech Impairment, Göteborg Psychological Reports, 2004, 34, No. 2. A theory of mind (ToM) refers to the ability to impute mental states to oneself and others. It has been argued that defic its in this ability are specific to individuals with autism. Recent studies on children with other communicative impairments, however, cast doubt on this suggested specific relationship. A study that investigated understanding of a range of mental states within a single group of normally developed participants suggested a three-stage model of development of ToM. Using this model a group of seven children with cerebral palsy and severe speech impairment were tested on a range of tasks requiring ToM. The findings suggest that the children in this group follow a normal pattern of development, but with a considerable delay com- pared with children without disability. The findings also cast further doubt on the suggested specific relationship between deficits in ToM and autism, showing that children with other disabilities also experience problems within this area, albeit be it not for the same reasons. Key words: cerebral palsy, physical impairment, speech impairment, theory of mind
No. 2:34,2 On a very general level, cognitive development could be described as a process by which a more and more abstract attitude to the world is attained, reminding of Piaget’s view on development. Even though the actual term ‘theory of mind’ is not mentioned directly in Piaget’s work, the child’s egocentric thinking and speech was at the very heart of it. These concepts resemble the theory of mind conception, only much more vague. The term ‘theory of mind’ (ToM), as it is used within the field of psychology, originates from a paper by Premack and Woodruff (1978). It refers to the ability to impute mental states to oneself and to others, i.e. the ability to understand that oneself and other people have thoughts, beliefs and emotions, and that these also govern our behaviour in different situations (Tager-Flusberg, Baron-Cohen & Cohen, 1993). The understanding of false belief has become the critical test of whether a child has developed a ToM or not. The reason for this is that if a child does not understand that people can hold false beliefs they do not really understand beliefs at all. In order to understand that beliefs are simply representations of the world, not exact copies, one has to understand that beliefs can also be false, they can be ‘misrepresentations’ (Hala & Carpendale, 1997). In 1983 Wimmer and Perner published a landmark paper in which they designed a so-called false-belief task which was a story acted out for the child with the help of dolls and toys. In order to demonstrate conclusively that someone attributes belief to another, we must show that they are able to ascribe to the other beliefs that are false, or at least different from their own. Otherwise we would not know whether they were genuinely attributing beliefs to the other or simply assuming that the other shared their own beliefs (Astington & Gopnik, 1991). In Wimmer and Perner’s false-belief task things are arranged so that the child’s beliefs are true, i.e. they reflect the way the world is, and an other’s beliefs are false. The child is then asked how that other person will act in the particular situation. If the children can recognise that the other will act on the basis of his or her false beliefs, then we can be reasonably certain that they attribute beliefs to the other (Astington & Gopnik, 1991). The results in the Wimmer and Perner (1983) study and in subsequent studies (e.g. Perner, Leekam & Wimmer, 1987; Sodian, 1991 etc.) showed that typically developing four-year-olds managed to solve the task and the acquisition of understanding of false belief around four years of age is by now a highly robust and much replicated finding (Astington & Gopnik, 1991; Perner, Leekam & Wimmer, 1987). A lot of the early research on ToM was carried out within the field of autism. The first study on ToM in children with autism was published in 1985 (Baron-Cohen, Leslie & Frith). The results from this, and from many studies to follow, showed that children with autism have great difficulty solving tasks requiring a ToM. Other clinical groups have also been tested, e.g. children with Down’s syndrome (Baron-Cohen et al. 1985; Baron-Cohen, 1989a), and children with mental disabilities of mixed aetiology (Baron-Cohen, 1989b). As none of these groups have exhibited difficulties in solving ToM-related tasks, it has been argued that deficits in ToM are specific to autism (Baron- Cohen, 1991a). There are studies, however, which fail to replicate the results of Baron-Cohen and others, studies which show that children with autism perform nearly as well as non- disabled children on first order ToM tasks, i.e. tasks that require the child to infer false belief to another (in so-called second order ToM tasks the child is required to understand what beliefs another person will infer to a third person) (Prior, Dahlstrom & Squires, 1990; Dahlgren & Trillingsgaard, 1996). Recent studies have also shown that children with other communicative disabilities have difficulties in solving tasks requiring a ToM, e.g. deaf children without early exposure to sign language (Peterson & Siegal, 1995; 1999; Steeds,
No. 2:34,3 Rowe & Dowker, 1997; Russell, Hosie, Gray, Scott & Hunter, 1998), children with visual impairments (McAlpine & Moore, 1995) and children with developmental language delay (Iarocci, Della-Cioppa, Randolph & Wohl, 1997). One of the major accounts of how children develop a ToM assigns a special role to pretence. Many theorists claim that pretend play and false belief are based on similar mental representation abilities (Forguson & Gopnik, 1988; Perner, 1988; Wimmer, Hogrefe & Sodian, 1988; Leslie, 1994). Others claim that understanding of the mind depends on a social- linguistic intelligence, which develops in social interaction with others (Lillard, 1994). It has also been suggested, as in the case of deaf children (Peterson & Siegal, 1995; 1999), that a lack of exposure to, and participation in, conversation about mental states could be responsible for the delayed development of a ToM. Several studies have also found linguistic competence to be an important factor in developing a ToM (Tager-Flusberg & Sullivan, 1994; Jenkins & Astington, 1996). Studies of atypical populations have given further evidence to the suggestion that linguistic ability and ToM understanding are associated with one another. One example of this is that autistic children who do pass false belief tasks also score higher on a number of measures of linguistic skills than do autistic children who fail these tasks (Eisenmajer & Prior, 1991; Happé, 1995; Sparrevohn & Howie, 1995; Dahlgren & Trillingsgaard, 1996). It has also been suggested that Semantic-pragmatic language disorder involves a severe deficit in this area. Phonological-syntactic language disorder may also be associated with poorly developed ToM skills (Shields, Varley, Broks & Simpson, 1996). Researchers have also hypothesised that ‘processing capacity’ may be related to false-belief understanding. For instance Olson (1993) argue that the acquisition of false- belief understanding is related to an increase in children’s working memory capacity. Due to lack of vocalisations, as well as to motor dysfunctions, children with cerebral palsy (CP) and severe speech impairment (SSI) often experience less spontaneous contacts with the environment and their potential for active manipulation of objects is far less than those of their peers. They have a limited capacity for independent pretence play and for interacting and playing with other children. Their contribution to discourse in conversational situations is also often limited (Light, Collier & Parnes, 1985; Hjelmquist & Dahlgren Sandberg, 1996; Falkman, Dahlgren Sandberg & Hjelmquist, 2002). These circumstances are all highly relevant from a ToM perspective. Earlier studies have shown that children with cerebral palsy and SSI achieve lower scores on tests of working memory compared to children without disability matched for sex and mental age (Dahlgren Sandberg, 1996), and at the same time they exhibit difficulties related to communicative skills which require a ToM, such as referential communication (Dahlgren Sandberg, Dahlgren & Hjelmquist, 2004). Considering the importance of ToM as a tool facilitating social and communicative interaction with others, it seems reasonable to predict that if children with SSI have a delayed development of ToM they would most likely also experience communication problems in everyday social situations, additional to those arising from difficulties with speech and language. Results from earlier studies confirm that children with cerebral palsy and SSI have difficulties in taking the point of view of the listener, and that they also have trouble initiating and participating in communicative interaction (Light et al. 1985; Dahlgren Sandberg & Hjelmquist, 1996; Falkman, et al., 2002). Together these aspects make studies of children with cerebral palsy and SSI especially interesting from a ToM perspective. In an earlier study, a group of six pre-school children with cerebral palsy and SSI, all with a mental age of more than four years and within normal range of intelligence, was compared to a group of six children without disability. Results from this study showed
No. 2:34,4 that only two out of six children in the disability group managed to pass the first order ToM task, whereas all six did so in the comparison group (Dahlgren, Dahlgren Sandberg & Hjelmquist, 2003). The aim of the present study was to further explore the ability to solve tasks requiring a ToM in a group of children with severe cerebral palsy and SSI, using a wider range of tasks. It seemed reasonable to predict that these children would have problems solving this kind of tasks. This assumption was based on the fact that earlier studies have suggested that children with SSI have difficulties in several areas that have been put forward as important in developing a ToM, such as linguistic ability, communicative interaction and working memory. Method Participants The children participating in this study were originally selected for a study on different aspects of communication in children with SSI (Dahlgren Sandberg, 1996). Seven young school children, one boy and six girls, with severe cerebral palsy participated in the present study. They all had a medical diagnosis of anarthria or dysarthria. Dysarthria meant that the children could express ‘yes’ and ‘no’ orally, but apart from this no intelligible oral communication was possible (Table 1a and 1b). None of the children could walk without support. They all needed help eating and getting dressed. At the time of the present study all children used Bliss as a major communication aid, but a majority also used other forms of augmentative and alternative communication (AAC). In one case this meant using manual signs. In all other cases it was a question of using eye-gaze or different forms of pre-linguistic communication such as facial expressions or unintelligible vocalisations. No other graphic modes of communication were used (Table 1). Three of the children attended regular schools while four attended special schools for disabled children. None of the children met the criteria for autism. A comparison group of children without disability matched for sex and mental age by the use of Raven’s progressive matrices, coloured version (Raven, 1965), was also included in the study. However, as all the children in the comparison group performed at ceiling on all ToM-tasks no further analysis will be performed comparing the two groups. Table 1a. Participant Characteristics, Group of Children with SSI Partici- Sex CA1 MA2 IQ Cp Speech pant Diagnosis Disorder 1 F 9:1 9:3 102 Athetosis, Dysarthria Dystonia 2 F 11:4 7:6 66 Hemiplegia Anarthria 3 F 9:11 6:0 61 Diplegia Dysarthria 4 F 9:2 7:4 79 Dystonia Anarthria 5 M 10:4 9:0 87 Dystonia Anarthria 6 F 11:1 7:6 68 Diplegia Dysarthria 7 F 10:6 6:6 62 Diplegia Anarthria
No. 2:34,5 Table 1b. Participant Characteristics, Group of Children with SSI Partici- Modes of Intelligi- Use of Bliss as Use of Number of Other modes of pant expressing ‘yes’ and bility Bliss in Bliss symbols communication ‘no’ years used 1 Body movement, Hardly Complement and parallel1,5 100-199 Facial clear sounds, very intelligible to other modes of expressions, seldom fails communication speech sounds, eye-gaze 2 Clear sounds, very No speech Complement and parallel 3 30-99 Manual signs, seldom fails to other modes of eye-gaze communication 3 Clear sounds, never Hardly Complement and parallel 1 30-99 Body movement, fails intelligible to other modes of facial expressions, communication manual signs, speech sounds, eye-gaze 4 Body movement, Hardly Primary mode of 2 100-199 Gestures, manual clear sounds, never intelligible communication signs, speech fails sounds, eye-gaze 5 Body movement, No speech Primary mode 2 100-199 Facial gestures, very expressions, eye- seldom fails gaze 6 Clear sounds, never Hardly Complement and parallel 2 100-199 Speech sounds, fails intelligible to other modes of eye-gaze communication 7 Gestures, never fails No speech Complement and parallel 4 400-499 Gestures, manual to other modes of signs, eye-gaze communication Materials and procedures The children’s linguistic capacity was measured by using the SIT (Språkligt Impressivt Test), a test of verbal comprehension on a semantic level (Hellquist, 1982). The test loosely corresponds to the internationally better-known TROG (Bishop, 1989). The children’s task was to point at the one picture out of three that they thought corresponded to a sentence just read by the experimenter. The variables included in the test were word classes, inflections and complexity of constructions. A test for syntactic knowledge that was an elaboration of a test of ‘syntactic acceptability: judgement and correction’ constructed by Nauclér & Magnusson (1985) was also used. It consisted of nine phrases that were read out loud to the children, four with correct syntax and five with syntax intended to approximate a child’s way of speaking. A photograph of a woman and a 2-year-old child looking at photographs was shown and the children were asked to tell which of the comments the child made and which were made by the woman. The Digit Span subtest of the WISC (Wechsler, 1977) was used as a measure of verbal short-term memory. The children with SSI repeated the numbers read out loud by the experimenter by pointing at figures printed on their Bliss charts. A visuo-spatial test of short-term memory was also included. This was the so-called Corsi blocks task (Rapala & Brady, 1990) where blocks were placed on a sheet of paper. The number of blocks placed on the paper started at four and continued up to nine blocks. The experimenter pointed at the blocks at a slow pace in random order. The children’s task was to repeat the pointing. Descriptive results for each participant (in the group of children with SSI) on the memory, linguistic and cognitive Scores can be found in Table 2.
No. 2:34,6 Table 2 Descriptive Results for Each Participant (in the group of children with SSI), Memory, Linguistic and Cognitive Scores Participant 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 SITa 46 45 42 43 46 43 35 b N&M - 8 7 6 8 9 8 Corsi blocksc 9 6 5 7 7 6 0 d Digit span 5 5 4 4 5 3 3 Ravene 27 19 16 20 26 20 17 Maximum Scores: 46a, 9b, 9c, 9d, 36e Gopnik and Slaughter (1991) have, after having investigated understanding of a range of mental states within a single group of non-disabled children, suggested a three-stage sequence in children’s development of understanding of mental states: Stage 1: Pretence, perception and imagination; Stage 2: Desire and intention, and Stage 3: Knowledge and belief. This sequence was tested further in a study by Baron-Cohen (1991b) and was found to fit the pattern of results for children with mental retardation, but not for children with autism who seem to be deviant as well as delayed in their development of ToM. So far, studies in this field have frequently assessed ToM using a single task. Using a series of tasks, however, allow us to look at children’s patterns of acquisition. By examining descriptions of individual patterns we can also gain insights into how false belief understanding relates to other areas of cognitive and social development (Jenkins & Astington, 1996). The different ToM tasks included in the study were selected partly on the basis that they would test the understanding of the mental states included in Gopnik and Slaughter’s (1991) developmental model of understanding of mental states. The tasks were also chosen because they have been widely used in previous ToM-research and because they, in addition to enabling a comparison with data from groups previously tested, also have a number of unique advantages as a measure of ToM in children without, or with very little, productive language skills. These advantages include a readily comprehensible story line supplemented by different props (a puppet play, other toys, pictures etc), a simple vocabulary, and the possibility of a completely nonverbal response mode (Baron-Cohen, 1992). All material used was adapted so that it could be used both with children using the spoken language and children with SSI. The tests were given to each child individually at home or at school with a teacher, an assistant or a parent present. The parent or assistant was present partly to make the child feel more comfortable and partly in case the experimenter had trouble interpreting the child’s communication. The tests were given without a time limit and presented to each child in approximately the same order, priority was however given to factors such as keeping the child motivated and not too tired. The children with SSI were allowed to choose whatever means of communication they were most comfortable with in answering the test questions. This resulted in ‘yes’ and ‘no’ occasionally being given orally, in all other cases answers were provided by pointing to materials used or using their Bliss board. All sessions were video recorded so that they could be reviewed again at a later time. This made it possible for both the first and the second author to score the tests independently in order to obtain a reliability score. The mental state tasks were scored as either a pass or a failure. In order to pass a task the child had to answer correctly both the built in control questions and the actual test question. If a child failed to answer correctly
No. 2:34,7 any of the control questions the test was scored as failed even if the child answered the actual test question correctly. After having scored the tests independently the first and second authors disagreed on only one test item for one participant. A discussion between the two authors, together with an additional analysis of the video recording, however, resulted in full agreement being reached. Pretend play Due to the children’s speech and motor impairments their understanding of pretend play was difficult to assess. Parts of a design by Leslie (1994) was, however, adapted and used. Two plastic cups were placed on the table in front of the child and two small teddy bears were introduced. The experimenter pretended to fill one of the cups with juice, and then said: ‘Look’!, picked up one of the cups and turned it upside down, shook it for a bit, then replaced it next to the other cup. The child was then asked to point to the empty cup (both cups were of course really empty throughout). The experimenter then pretended to fill the empty cup again, but this time one of the teddy bears took the cup and poured the drink over the other bear. Following this it was suggested that she was now in need of a bath. The experimenter made movements suggesting the removal of her clothes and each time put them down on the same part of the table. After having had a bath it was time to put her clothes back on and the child was asked to point to wherever the experimenter had put her clothes. Perception, level 1 The first perception task was modelled after Flavell, Everett, Craft and Flavell’s (1981) level 1 perspective task, but asked about the child’s own perception rather than the perception of another person (Gopnik & Slaughter, 1991). A piece of cardboard was shown to the child with only one side visible. On one side of the card was a picture of a car and on the other side was a picture of a plane. The subject was first shown one side of the card and was asked what picture he or she could see. The answer was given by pointing to the corresponding picture on another piece of cardboard put on the table in front of the child, which showed pictures of a car, a plane, a bird and a bicycle. The card was then turned around so that the child could see the other picture. He or she was then asked, ‘Now what picture can you see’?. Finally, the experimenter asked the test question: ‘When I first asked you, before I turned the card over, what picture did you see? (Did you see a car or a plane?)’. Perception, level 2 The second perception task was modelled after Flavell, Everett, Croft and Flavell’s (1981) level 2 perspective task, but the child was asked about another person’s perception of a picture, as well as his/ her own. The child, sitting opposite the experimenter, was shown a drawn picture of a pig and was then asked: ‘How do you see this pig? Standing up or lying down’? followed by the question: ‘How do you think I see the pig? Standing up or lying down’? Answers were provided by pointing to the pig’s feet or his back. The experimenter then turned the picture upside down so that the pig appeared to be lying on its back. The same two questions were asked once more and then the test question was asked: ‘When I first asked you, before I turned the picture around, how did you see the pig then? (Did you see him standing up or lying down?)’.
No. 2:34,8 Droodles (whole-part) Depending on what prior information they have obtained, people may acquire different information from the same perceptual experience. In order to assess the children’s understanding of this an uninterpretable picture, so called ‘droodles’ (Perner & Davies, 1991) was used. In this case a black and white drawn picture of a cat was presented to the child. The experimenter then covered the whole picture, except for the tip of the cat’s tail, with a piece of paper. The child was now asked the following question: ‘If your mum (or any other person not present in the room) was shown this picture, would she be able to tell that it was a picture of a cat’?. If the child’s answer was yes the questions ‘Has she seen this picture before’? and ‘Can she be sure that it is a cat’? were asked. Desire In the desire task the participant formed a desire, and the desire was then satiated so that it changed. The children were shown two boxes and were then asked which one they wanted to open. After they had looked inside their first choice and played with the object it contained (a seashell or a small teddy bear), that box was closed and they were asked to choose again. The same procedure now followed with the second box, i.e. the child opened the box to look inside and was allowed to play with the content after which the box was closed and the experimenter asked the test question: ‘When I first asked you, before we opened any of the boxes, which box did you want to open? (Did you want to open this one or this one?)’. There was no delay between the initial state and the subsequent state, the child’s desire was immediately changed which meant that difficulties would not reflect a memory problem (Gopnik & Slaughter, 1991). First order belief attribution The test for first order belief attribution (i.e. the ability to think about someone else’s thinking) was an adaptation of the well-known smarties test (Perner, Leekam & Wimmer, 1987). A Winegum box was shown to the children. The children were first asked what they thought the box contained. After a look in the box they discovered that the box did in fact not contain winegum but pencils. After the box was closed again the children were asked what someone who had not looked inside would think it contained, the correct answer being “winegum”, “sweets” or some other equivalent word. If the child hesitated the prompt ‘would they think it contains sweets or pencils’? was given. This is a compelling way of demonstrating difficulties with false belief as the child experiences how the misleading situation creates a false belief in him/ herself before an attribution has to be made to the other person (Perner, Frith, Leslie & Leekam, 1989). Finally the question: ‘when I first asked you, before we looked inside, what did you think was in the box’ was asked. In addition to answering the belief question correctly, the correct answer (i.e. again “winegum”, “sweets” or some other equivalent word) had to be given to this control question in order for the child to score “pass” on the belief task. Second order belief attribution To test the children’s ability to make second-order belief attributions (i.e. their ability to think about another person’s thinking about a third person’s thinking) the
No. 2:34,9 procedure was exactly the same as in the study by Baron-Cohen (1989a): The experimenter laid out the toy village on the table in front of the child, making sure that the child could see it properly. The experimenter then told the following story, moving the dolls and the ice-cream van accordingly: This is Olle and Eva. They live in this village. Here they are in the park. Along comes the ice-cream man. Olle would like to buy an ice-cream but has left his money at home. He is very sad. ”Don’t worry” says the ice-cream man, ”you can go home and get your money and buy some ice-cream later. ”Oh, good” says Olle. ”I’ll be back here later to buy an ice-cream”. Control question (1): Where did the ice-cream man say that he would be all afternoon? So Olle goes home. He lives in this house. Now, the ice-cream man says: ”I am going to drive my van to the church to see if I can sell my ice-cream outside there instead”. Control question (2): Where did the ice-cream man say he was going? Control question (3): Did Olle hear that? The ice-cream man drives over to the church. On his way he passes Olle’s house. Olle sees him and says, ”Where are you going?” The ice-cream man says, ”I’m going to sell my ice- cream outside the church”. And off he drove to the church. Control question (4): Where did the ice-cream man tell Olle he was going? Control question (5): Does Eva know that the ice-cream man has talked to Olle? Now Eva goes home. She lives in this house. Then she goes over to Olle’s house. She knocks on the door and says ”Is Olle in?” ”No”, says his father, ”he’s gone out to buy an ice-cream”. Belief question: Where does Eva think that Olle has gone to buy an ice- cream? (Correct answer: the park) Control question (6): Where did Olle really go to buy his ice cream? (Correct answer: the church) Control question (7): Where was the ice-cream man in the beginning? (Correct answer: the park) Results Table 3 presents the results for each child with SSI on the mental-state tasks. As already mentioned, the children in the control group all performed at ceiling level on these tasks. In order to pass the mental-state tasks the children had to answer correctly on both the control questions and the actual test question. Our results from the children with SSI can be summarised descriptively by saying that with only a few exceptions all the children passed the pretend, perception, droodle and desire tasks, correct answers were given in 80 % of the cases. The false-belief tasks, however, proved to be more difficult, with correct answers in only 50 % of the cases. This result is in accordance with the Gopnik and Slaughter (1991) three-stage model of development of ToM, which states that false belief is one of the mental states for which understanding is last to develop.
No. 2:34,10 Table 3 Descriptive Results for Each Participant, Mental State Tasks Participant 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Pretend pass pass pass pass pass pass pass Perception 1 pass pass pass pass pass pass fail Perception 2 pass pass pass pass pass fail fail Droodles pass fail pass pass pass pass fail Desire pass fail pass pass pass pass fail False-belief 1 pass pass fail pass pass fail fail False-belief 2 pass fail fail pass pass fail fail Participant characteristics for those who passed and failed the false belief tasks respectively are presented in Tables 4a and 4b. Despite the small sample size, a pattern of differences between those who passed and those who failed the false-belief tasks was still discernible. Four children out of seven passed the first order false-belief task, while three children failed the same task. The children who failed the first order false- belief task were also those with the lowest IQs. They also achieved lower scores on the memory tasks (digit span and corsi blocks) and on the test of verbal comprehension, semantic level (the SIT). The second order false-belief task was, as expected, somewhat more difficult. Three children passed the second order false-belief task, while four children failed. The same pattern of results was shown for those children who failed the second order false-belief task as for those who failed the first order false-belief task, i.e. they had lower IQ and also achieved lower scores on the test of verbal comprehension (SIT) and on the memory tasks. It is, however, important to keep in mind that their mental age was above the 4-5 year level, which is the typical age for passing the first-order false-belief task. Table 4a Participant Characteristics of “Passers” and “Failers”* on the First-Order False-Belief Tasks. MA CA IQ + - + - + - 1 9:3 9:1 102 2 7:6 11:4 66 3 6:0 9:11 61 4 7:4 9:2 79 5 9:0 10:4 87 6 7:6 11:1 68 7 6:6 10:6 62 Mean 8:3 6:8 9:11 10:4 84 64 SIT N&M Corsi bl. Digit sp + - + - + - + - 1 46 - 9 5 2 45 8 6 5 3 42 7 5 4 4 43 9 6 3 5 46 8 7 5 6 43 6 7 4 7 35 8 0 3 Mean 45 40 7,75 8 7,25 3,67 4,75 3,33 * - = fail, + = pass
No. 2:34,11 Table 4b Participant Characteristics of “Passers” and “Failers”* on the Second-Order False-Belief Tasks. MA CA IQ + - + - + - 1 9:3 9:1 102 2 7:6 11:4 66 3 6:0 9:11 61 4 7:4 9:2 79 5 9:0 10:4 87 6 7:6 11:1 68 7 6:6 10:6 62 Mean 8:6 6:11 9:6 10:7 89 65 SIT N&M Corsi bl. Digit sp + - + - + - + - 1 46 - 9 5 2 45 8 6 5 3 42 7 5 4 4 43 9 6 3 5 46 8 7 5 4 6 43 6 7 4 7 35 8 0 3 Mean 46 41 8,33 7,5 7,33 4,5 5 3,5 * = fail, + = pass Discussion The results of this study should be reviewed in the light of the performance of the control group where all the children performed at ceiling on all the ToM tasks included in the study, a result that is not very surprising, but rather one that could be expected considering the mental age of the children. Children with a typical development can accurately complete first order false-belief tasks at the age of approximately 4 years. As indicated in Table 1 the children with SSI included in this study had a mental age of 6 years or above, as measured by using the Raven progressive matrices (Raven, 1965). The results also provide further evidence that deficits in the ability to solve tasks requiring a ToM is not in fact specific for children with autism, but can also be found in children with other communicative impairments. The children with cerebral palsy and SSI who, quite contrary to children with autism, showed an obvious interest in taking part in social and communicative interaction, although limited of course by their motor and communicative disabilities, still had difficulties solving the false-belief tasks. It is however important to keep in mind that just because different clinical groups show similar results on the ToM tasks, it is not to say that the same mechanisms underlie the success or failure on these tasks. One of the key questions in this field of research is whether the development of a ToM is dependent on some innate cognitive structure of the brain (eg. Leslie, 1988, 1994), or whether it is an ability which is acquired through social interaction with others (eg. Astington & Gopnik, 1991; Lillard, 1994). The difficulties that the children with SSI experienced with the false-belief tasks do not seem to be explicable in terms of general problems with motivation. The children all showed great enthusiasm, worked hard and seemed to enjoy the assessment sessions. Instead, the difficulties in solving mental state tasks in the group of children with SSI could be an effect of the experimental procedure per se. Motor disabilities and possible defects in working memory (Dahlgren Sandberg, 1996) might interact and make it impossible for them to solve the task, but not due to a genuine lack of ToM. However, memory deficits can be ruled out as an explanation for the results. All of the children answered the memory and control questions within the mental state tasks correctly, yet
No. 2:34,12 failed to answer correctly the question that specifically tested their ability to attribute mental states. The development of a ToM in the children with SSI might also be delayed due to the communicative impairment and the overall dependence on others, not least for interpretation of communicative acts. Previous research has shown that children with severe motor disabilities and SSI have very limited ways of influencing their situation and initiate conversation. It has been suggested that a lack of exposure to conversation about mental states could be responsible for the low performance of deaf children on false belief tasks (Peterson & Siega l, 1995, 1999). This kind of lack of exposure to conversation about mental states could be true also for children with cerebral palsy and SSI. Previous research has shown that when the speaking partner initiates conversation, it is often with a specific purpose in mind, such as feeding, guiding, caring for et c. Very seldom is simple every day social contact or pretend playing together the sole purpose of the interaction (Harris, 1982). This, however, is an area where further research is needed. Another possible explanation could be low verbal competence. In an earlier study children with cerebral palsy and SSI performed significantly worse on a test of verbal comprehension compared to a group of children without disability (Dahlgren Sandberg & Hjelmquist, 1996), and a study by Dahlgren et al. (1996) showed that the difference in performance on ToM tasks between a group of children with high functioning autism and a group of children with Asperger’s syndrome disappeared when the two groups were matched for verbal IQ. The results of the present study also show that those who failed the false belief tasks achieved lower scores on the test of verbal comprehension (i.e. the SIT) as well. There are several possible explanations for the suggested relationship between language ability and false-belief understanding. One possibility is that standard methods of measuring children’s Tom abilities rely too heavily on children’s linguistic competence. In the standard task the children have to listen to the experimenter talk about some task materials, comprehend this input, process the experimenter’s questions about it, and make some response. Children may understand false belief but, because of the linguistic complexity of the tasks, be unable to demonstrate their understanding in this context. From this point of view, the children’s linguistic immaturity might result in task performance that masks their underlying competence. It is important, however, to remember that crucial to the original idea of studying ToM is that it should be possible to have a ToM, in particular a false belief, without having a language at all as the idea of ToM tasks was developed in the context of a discussion on how to study the mental capacities of nonhuman primates (Premack & Woodruff, 1978). When studying children linguistic communication is of course used. The question of whether the children ‘comprehend’ instructions is critical in this context. The task instructions that were used in the present study comprised linguistic constructions that were covered by the SIT test (Hellquist, 1982). The control questions did contain the mental state verb ‘think’ in one case (first belief attribution). Only if the child answered the control questions correctly, was the child’s answer to the ToM question included in the analysis, because a correct answer to the control question shows that the child has a correct comprehension of some aspects of the verb ‘think’. The child understands the meaning of the verb deep enough to enable correct pragmatic use of it, at least in certain contexts, such as the test question used. One could say that the ToM task shows whether the child, in the same context, has an even more advanced understanding of ‘think’, to the extent that the child understands that a person can think ‘wrong’, i.e. have a false belief. This constitutes the central part of the logic, and validity, of ToM tasks. All children in our study who are
No. 2:34,13 included in the results have thus showed some understanding of ‘think’ and the question is then, how many of these show an understanding of the ToM task (some do, some do not). Even more important, the remaining ToM tasks do not include any mental verbs at all. This again goes back to the original ideas behind ToM, that it should be possible to study ToM without talking about it, in particular not with mental verbs. In general, the rest of the linguistic aspects of the instructions and control questions were well within the ability of the children, as they were made up of simple constructions and a simple vocabulary. The children’s level of verbal comprehension would therefore not seem to be the primary explanation to their relatively low performance on the false belief tasks. The number of children in the group who passed the test for first order belief attribution had now increased slightly compared to the earlier study by Dahlgren et al. (1996), something which, together with the fact that almost all the children passed all mental state tasks, except false-belief, supports the idea of a delay rather than a deficiency in the development of a ToM. This result also fits with the Gopnik and Slaughter (1991) developmental sequence, which states that false belief is one of the mental states for which understanding is last to develop. This of course leaves us with the question of why this delay occurs. The fact that the children often have a severe motor dysfunction which prohibits them to move about freely and interact with the physical environment on their own terms, together with the fact that too often there is also a lack of sufficient means of communication, together with the difficulties in communicating with the child, often experienced among parents and other people close to the child, leads us to speculate that a lack of experience could be at the root of the problem. Without us even thinking about it typically developing children are every day provided with an enormous amount of experiences and opportunities to practice and improve their motor, communication, and social skills. This is not true in the same way for children with cerebral palsy. This raises the clinical issue of whether intervention could reduce the delay in ToM development. The ability to take someone else’s perspective, to understand that other people’s actions are governed by their thoughts, beliefs and feelings, is crucial in social interaction and communication between people, and inter-personal communication enhances this ability. It is therefore important not only to provide children with SSI with appropriate and sufficient communication aids, such as Bliss for example, but also to provide experiences and the tools with which to use communication aids in an efficient manner. The question of why the development of a ToM seems to be delayed in the group of children with cerebral palsy and SSI remains an important question for future research, and it would be interesting to test the various possible explanations for the findings empirically in subsequent investigations. In summary, although the results of this study must of course be interpreted with caution because of the small sample size, they give support to the idea that children with severe cerebral palsy and SSI are delayed, but not deficient, in acquiring a so called ToM, especially when looking at the results in relief to the results of the children without disability who were matched for mental and chronological age. Acknowledgements This paper is partially based on a presentation given at the 8th biennial conference of the international society for augmentative and alternative communication (ISAAC), August 1998, Dublin, Ireland. The study was supported by a grant from the Swedish Council for Social Research.
No. 2:34,14 References Astington, J. W., & Gopnik, A. (1991). Theoretical explanations of children’s understanding of mind. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 7-31. Baron-Cohen, S. (1989a). The autistic child’s theory of mind: A case of specific developmental delay. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 30, 285-298. Baron-Cohen, S. (1989b). Are autistic children behaviourists? An examination of their mental, physical and appearance-reality distinction. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 19, 579-600. Baron-Cohen, S. (1991a). The theory of mind deficit in autism: How specific is it? British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 301-314. Baron-Cohen, S. (1991b). The Development of a theory of mind in autism: Deviance and delay? Psychiatric Clinics of North America, 14 (1), 33-47. Baron-Cohen, S. (1992). The theory of mind hypothesis of autism: History and prospects of the idea. The Psychologist, 5, 9-12. Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A., & Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a ‘theory of mind’? Cognition, 21, 37-46. Bishop, D. V. M. (1989). Test of reception of grammar (2nd ed.). University of Manchester: The Author, Age and Cognitive Performance Research Centre Dahlgren, S.O., Dahlgren Sandberg, A., & Hjelmquist, E. (2003). The nonspecificity of theory of mind deficits. Evidence from children with communicative disabilities. Manuscript submitted for publication. Dahlgren, S.O., & Trillingsgaard, A. (1996). Theory of mind in non-retarded children with autism and Asperger´s syndrome. A research note. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 37, 759-763. Dahlgren Sandberg, A. (1996). Literacy abilities in nonvocal children with cerebral palsy. Doctoral dissertation, Department of psychology. Göteborg: Kompaniet. Dahlgren Sandberg A., Dahlgren , S. O., & Hjelmquist, E. (2004). Referential Communication in Children with Communicative Disabilities. Manuscript submitted for publication. Dahlgren Sandberg, A., & Hjelmquist, E. (1996). Phonologic awareness and literacy abilities in nonspeaking preschool children with cerebral palsy. Augmentative and Alternative Communication, 12, 138-153. Eisenmajer, R., & Prior, M. (1991). Cognitive linguistic correlates of ‘theory of mind’ ability in autistic children. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 351- 364. Falkman, K. W., Dahlgren Sandberg, A., & Hjelmquist, E. (2002). Preferred communication modes: Pre- linguistic and linguistic communication in nonspeaking pre-school children with cerebral palsy. International Journal of Language and Communication Disorders, 37, 59-68. Flavell, J. H., Everett, B. A., Croft, K., & Flave ll, E. R. (1981). Young children’s knowledge about visual perception: Further evidence for the Level 1 - Level 2 distinction. Developmental Psychology, 17, 99-103. Forguson, L., & Gopnik, A. (1988). The ontogeny of common sense. In Astington, J. W., Harris, P. L., & Olson, D. R. (Eds.). Developing Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gopnik, A., & Slaughter, V. (1991). Young children’s understanding of changes in their mental states. Child Development, 62, 98-110.
No. 2:34,15 Hala, S., & Carpendale, J. (1997). All in the mind: children’s understanding of mental life. In Hala (Ed.). The Development of Social Cognition. Hove, UK: Psychology Press Ltd. Happé, F.G.E. (1995. Understanding minds and metaphors: Insights from the study of figurative language in autism. Metaphor and Symbolic Activity, 10, 275-295. Harris, D. (1982). Communicative interaction processes involving nonvocal physically handicapped children. Topics in Language Disorders, 2, 21-37. Hellquist, B. (1982). SIT, Språkligt Impressivt Test för barn. (Assessment of language comprehension in children). Löddeköpinge, Sweden: Pedagogisk Design. Hjelmquist, E., & Dahlgren Sandberg, A. (1996). Sounds and silence: interaction in aided language use. In Stephen von Tetzchner & Mogens Hygum Jensen (Eds.), Augmentative and Alternative Communication. European Perspectives (pp.137- 152.). London: Whurr Publishers Ltd. Iarocci, G., Della-Cioppa, J., Randolph, B., & Wohl, E. (1997, April). Do Children with Developmental Language Delay have a Theory of Mind? Poster session presented at the Society for Research in Child Development, Washington, D.C. Jenkins, J. M., & Astington. J. W. (1996). Cognitive factors and family structure associated with theory of mind development in young children. Developmental Psychology, 32, 70-78. Leslie. A. M. (1988). Autistic children’s understanding of seeing, knowing and believing. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 6, 315-324. Leslie, A. M. (1994). Pretending and believing: issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition, 50, 211-238. Light, J., Collier, B., & Parnes, P. (1985). Communicative interaction between young nonspeaking physically disabled children and their primary caregivers: Part I- Discourse patterns. Augmentative and Alternative Communication, 10, 169-183. Lillard, A. (1994). Making sense of pretence. In C. Lewis, & P. Mitchell (Eds.), Children’s Early Understanding of Mind (pp. 211-231). Hove, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum. McAlpine, L. M., & Moore, C. L. (1995). The development of social understanding in children with visual impairments. Journal of Visual Impairment and Blindness, 89, 349-358. Nauclér, K., & Magnusson, E. (1985). Testningar inom projektet KOLOSS (Testing reading and writing abilities). Praktisk lingvistik nr 10, Department of linguistics, Lund, University, Lund. Olson, D. R. (1993). The development of representations: The origins of mental life. Canadian Psychology, 34, 1-14. Perner, J. (1988). Higher-order beliefs and intentions in children’s understanding of social interaction. In J. W. Astington, P. L. Harris & D. R . Olson (Eds.), Developing theories of mind (pp. 271-294). New York: Cambridge University Press. Perner, J., & Davies, G. (1991). Understanding the mind as an active information processor: Do young children have a ‘copy theory of mind’? Cognition, 39, 51-69. Perner, J., Frith, U., Leslie, A. M., & Leekam, R. (1989). Exploration of the autistic child’s theory of mind: Knowledge, belief, and communication. Child Development, 60, 689-700. Perner, J., Leekam, S., & Wimmer, H. (1987). Three- year-olds difficulty with false belief: The case for a conceptual deficit. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 5, 125-137. Peterson, C. C., & Siegal, M. (1995). Deafness, conversation and theory of mind. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 36, 459-474.
No. 2:34,16 Peterson, C. C., & Siegal, M. (1999). Representing inner worlds: Theory of mind in autistic, deaf, and normal hearing children. Psychological Science, 10, 126-129. Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 4, 515-526. Prior, M., Dahlstrom, B., & Squires, T. L. (1990). Autistic children’s knowledge of thinking feeling states in other people. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 31, 581-601. Rapala, M. M., & Brady, S. (1990). Reading ability and short-term memory: The role of phonological processing. Reading and Writing: An interdisciplinary Journal, 2, 1- 25. Raven, J. C. (1965). Guide to using the coloured progressive matrices. London: H. K. Lewis. Russell, P. A., Hosie, J. A., Gray, C. D., Scott, C., Hunter, N., Banks, J. S., & Macaulay, M. C. (1998). The Development of theory of mind in deaf children. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 39, 903-910. Shields, J., Varely, R., Broks, P., & Simpson, A. (1996). Social cognition in developmental language disorders and high- level autism. Developmental Medicine and Child Neurology, 38, 487-495. Sodian, B. (1991). The development of deception in young children. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9, 173-188. Sparrevohn, R.M, & Howie, P.M. (1995). Theory of mind in childen with autistic disorder: evidence of developmental progression and the role of verbal ability. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 36, 249-263. Steeds, L., Rowe, K., & Dowker, A. (1997). Deaf children’s understanding of beliefs and desires. Journal of Deaf Studies and Deaf Education, 2, 185-195. Tager-Flusberg, H., Baron-Cohen, S., & Cohen, D. (1993). An introduction to the debate.In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & D. Cohen (Eds.), Understanding other minds: Perspectives from autism. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. Tager-Flusberg, H., & Sullivan, K. (1994). Predicting and explaining behaviour: A comparison of autistic, mentally retarded and normal children. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 35, 1059-1075. Wechsler, D. (1977). Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children. 4th Ed. Eskilstuna, Sweden: Psykologiförlaget. Wimmer, H., Hogrefe, J., & Sodian, B. (1988). A second stage in children’s conception of mental life: Understanding informational accesses as origins of knowledge and belief. In J. W. Astington, P. L. Harris & D.R. Olson (Eds.). Developing Theories of Mind. (pp. 173-192). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13, 103-128.
No. 2:34,17
You can also read