Stories of the arithmetic infinite - Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS - UniPD
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
Stories of the arithmetic infinite Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Il punto di vista aritmetico, Venezia 12/11/2021 logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
I. Some apories of the potential infinite. I.1. Aristotle: distinction between the potential infinite and the actual infinite (Metaphysics IX, Physics III). Potential infinite (infinite in capacity): when a collection of things has no point where it ends. Actual infinite (infinite in effect): when an infinite collection of things is circumscribed, exists as a closed totality - banished by Aristotle. Geometry at Euclide’s time was a NOT the “science of abstract space" (this is a modern viewpoint), but the study of finite configurations which can be extended ad libitum, but remain finite. In medieval times, the actual infinite became a “metaphysical infinite", which had earthly manifestations only under rare and strict conditions (cf. the story of Tempier’s condemnations). Infinitum actu non datur. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
In order to appropriate and domesticate the infinite, mathematicians gradually - distinguished between infinite and absolute, - distinguished between infinitely small and infinitely large, - invented a notation and a calculus of the infinitely small before creating a concept of the continuum (and later of the actual infinite); meanwhile, constructed new geometric spaces that included the horizont (following the painters of the Renaissance). More radical than Aristotle, Zeno of Elea, following his master Parmenides, denied both motion and plurality. In anachronical notation, Zeno’s most famous paradox of dichotomy reads 1 1 1 ? 1+ + + + ··· = 2 2 4 8 - it took more than two millenaries to understand the · · · , and to logoslides conclude the equality = 2. Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
I.2. In the XVIIIth c., Euler considered some infinite sums of integers, such as: ? (i ) 1 + 2 + 4 + 8 + ··· = ∞ ? (ii ) 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + ··· = ∞ ? (iii ) 0! − 1! + 2! − 3! + 4! + · · · = ±∞, (n! = 1 · 2 · · · n), logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
and proposed alternative strange-looking answers: (i ) 1 + 2 + 4 + 8 + · · · = −1 1 (ii ) 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + ··· = − 12 ∞ e −t Z (iii ) 0! − 1! + 2! − 3! + 4! + · · · = dt . 0 1+t logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Case (i ) is based on the counting method by generating series: 1 1 + 2x + 4x 2 + 8x 3 + · · · = 1 − 2x (then set x = 1). Case (iii ) uses generating series again: ŷ = 0!x − 1!x 2 + 2!x 3 − 3!x 4 + 4!x 5 + · · · , which satisfies the differential equation x 2 ŷ 0 + ŷ = x . ŷ is the asymptotic expansion (Euler writes “evolutio") of the R ∞ −t /x solution y = 0 e1+t dt in the complex plane deprived from the negative real half-line. (De seriebus divergentibus 1746-1760; contains five other justifications of (iii )). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
For (ii ), with the same method, x x + 2x 2 + 3x 3 + 4x 4 + · · · = (1 − x )2 gives ∞ at x = 1. To get a finite answer, Euler used a finer type of an n−s instead of an x n . P P generating series: For an = 1, this corresponds to the Riemann zeta function ζ(s) = n−s (known to Euler for s an integer). P Formula (ii ) which deals formally with ζ(−1) is then obtained by relating ζ(−1) to 1 1 π2 ζ(2) = 1 + + + · · · = . 22 32 6 (Remarques sur un beau rapport entre les séries des puissances tant directes que réciproques, 1749). logoslides This is much deeper than (i ) or (iii ): a full proof, starting with making good sense of ζ(−1), waited 120 years (Riemann). Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Morals of the story: - Euler not only distinguished perfectly between convergent and divergent series, but he had a working knowledge of asymptotic expansions, well ahead of his time, and a phenomenal intuition. - There are different ways of resumming divergent series, relevant in different context. (Euler also considered 1 + 1 + 1 + ··· for instance, explained “the cause of great dissent among mathematicians of whom some deny and others affirm that such a sum can be found", but prefered to consider this sum as ∞ rather than to interpret it artificially, without context, as ζ(0) = − 21 ). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
- Divergence is even more unwanted in Physics as in Mathematics. A typical case is Quantum Field Theory, which systematically produces some unwanted infinities. Systematic ways have been found to resum these divergent series (indexed by Feynman diagrams): renormalization techniques - of which Euler’s techniques are toy models. Astoundly, the results of these formal manipulations turn out to be incredibly close to the experimental data. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
I.3. Another way to give sense to sums like 1 + 2 + 4 + 8 + · · · or 0! − 1! + 2! − 3! + 4! + · · · is via p-adic analysis (Hensel 1897). What is it? p: prime number. Expansion in basis p : n = a0 + a1 p + · · · ak pk ∈ N, 0 6 ai < p. Invert p: a−` p−` + · · · + ak pk ∈ N[ p1 ]. “Completions" (in two completely different ways): `→∞ R (expansion of real numbers in base p), k →∞ Qp (field of p-adic numbers). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
For instance - 1 + 2 + 4 + 8 + · · · does converge 2-adically to −1. - 0! − 1! + 2! − 3! + 4! + · · · can be considered as a p-adic number for every prime number p, but nothing is known about these numbers. - There is also a p-adic story “related to" 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + · · · ... Nowadays, p-adic numbers pervade Number Theory (see later). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Some apories of the actual infinite. II. Some apories of the actual infinite. II.1. Here is a solitary game, invented by the logician Goodstein, which is played with numbers. It is based on hereditary base-b notation: one writes n in base b, then writes all exponents in base b, and so on... For instance, in hereditary base-2 notation, 2 25 = 22 + 22+1 + 1. Now, one picks an integer n > 0, writes is in hereditary base-2. 2 One changes all 2’s in 3’s (for instance 25 = 22 + 22+1 + 1 3 becomes 33 + 33+1 + 1 = 7625597485069), and one substracts 1. Next step: one writes this number in hereditary base-3, changes all logoslides 3’s in 4’s, substracts 1, and so on. The game ends if one eventually gets 0. Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
For instance, starting from n = 2, one gets 21 31 − 1 = 2 2−1=1 0: the game ends at the third step. Starting from n = 3, one gets 3 = 21 + 1 31 + 1 − 1 = 3 41 − 1 = 3 2 1 0: the game ends at the fifth step. Starting from n = 4, one gets 4 = 22 33 − 1 = 26 = 2.32 + 2.31 + 2 2.42 + 2.41 + 1 = 2 1 41 2.5 + 2.5 = 60 83 . . ., and the game ends only at the 402653211 far far away step 3.(2 − 1). For bigger n’s, this worsens up to the point that no known system of notation for big numbers is able to express the growth of the sequence. Still, Goodstein proved that the game always ends. The mouse which nibbles 1 at each step finally wins against the huge jumps which arise from changing base b to base b + 1! logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Goodstein’s proof uses the infinite, in fact the smallest countable ordinal ω = N: he observes that writing the m-th term G(n)m of the sequence (starting from n) in hereditary base m + 1, and changing all m + 1 into ω , one obtains a decreasing function in m. For instance, G(4)1 = 4 = 22 ω ω , G(4)2 = 26 = 2 1 2.3 + 2.3 + 2 2ω + 2ω + 2 < ω ω . 2 This sequence thus reaches 0, and so does the original sequence. Isn’t there a more standard proof, by induction? NO (Kirby, Paris): whereas the step at which the game ends is computable (say, by a Turing machine), the theory of finite arithmetic (as devised by Peano) is unable to prove that the game actually ends. The game is a reflection in the finite world of the axiom of infinity. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
II.2. The presence of the infinite behind the finite is not limited to such strange examples. The standard technique of generating series to enumerate a hierarchy of finite configurations Cn uses studies the series y = ∞ n P 1 |Cn |x , the functional or differential equations it satisfies. Even if one does not know how to solve the equation, asymptotic analysis helps to control the behaviour of y at ∞ and get estimates for |Cn |. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Example. If Cn is the set of partitions of n (for n = 4, C4 = {(1 + 1 + 1 + 1, 1 + 1 + 2, 1 + 3, 2 + 2, 4}), it turns out that X∞ y = 1/( (−1k )x k (3k −1)/2 ), −∞ and √ |Cn | ∼ (4 3 · n)−1 exp(π (2n/3)) p (Hardy, Ramanujan). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
II.3. Back to the actual infinite: a few words about those famous large cardinals. Starting from ℵ0 = |N| (the smallest infinite cardinal), one forms the ladder ℵ 2ℵ0 ℵ0 , 2ℵ0 , 22 0 , 22 ,... Two questions: 1) at the bottom of the ladder, are there intermediate cardinals between the first two rungs (i.e. between the countable and the continuum); more generally, between consecutive rungs? 2) And are there any cardinals above the top of the ladder? logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Question (1) is undecided (Cantor was in favour of NO). The usual axomatic of set theory ZFC is too weak to decide (Gödel, Cohen). This does not settle or discard the issue, but raises instead the problem of completing ZFC in order to decide it. Recent advances in set theory (Woodin...) seem to show that a precise answer to Question (2) is a key to Question (1). The top of the ladder impacts on the bottom: the existence of large cardinals (with some properties, e.g. with respect to partitions) impacts the complexity of subsets of the continuum (Cantor’s starting point). Moral of the story: higher infinities shed light on lower ones, and conversely, via a dialectic between existence and complexity. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
III. The ascent to the absolute (Lautman) [A vista toward more contemporary mathematics, and a glimpse of a new spring in Number Theory] III.1. let P ∈ Q[x ] be an irreducible polynomial, with roots α1 , . . . , αn ∈ C. In modern terms, Galois (∼ 1830) attached to P the group of automorphisms of the field Q(αi )i =1,...,n viewed as a group of substitutions of α1 , . . . , αn , and establishes a correspondence between subfields and subgroups. One may also consider the field of all algebraic numbers: Q̄ ⊂ C. The group of automorphisms of Q̄ is the absolute Galois group of Q, denoted GQ . There are “projections" GQ → Aut (Q(αi )) for every P, and GQ is the inverse limit of this system of projections, whence a natural topology: GQ is a compact (profinite) group. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
A single object, GQ therefore encodes the properties of all algebraic numbers at the same time. Furthermore, one can perform new constructions on this object: one can study GQ through its “continous linear representations" and their “deformations", and thereby get a lot of information about GQ (cf. Wiles’ proof of Fermat). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Still... - one does not know how to describe/construct any element beyond the two obvious elements: identity id and complex conjugation c, - one does not know the structure of GQ . Q ⊂ Q(µ∞ ) := Q(exp(2i π/n))n∈N ) ⊂ Q̄. Then GQ is an extension of the abelian group Aut (Q(µ∞ )) ∼ = Ẑ∗ by Gal (Q̄/Q(µ∞ )). Shafarevich’s conjecture: Gal (Q̄/Q(µ∞ )) is a free (profinite) group. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
III.2. One may replace the base field Q by other fields: - GR = {id, c} (since any polynomial with real coefficients has all its roots in C) - GQp : unlike GQ , one can construct many elements, and in fact topological generators, and the structure of this topological group is “known", but very complicated (Winberg, Jannsen...) Bijection N ↔ Fp [x ] : a0 + a1 p + · · · + ak pk 7→ a0 + a1 x + · · · ak x k (does not preserve algebraic structures: on the RHS, addition is performed without carrying). Then invert p: a−` p−` + · · · + ak pk ∈ N[ p1 ] ↔ Fp [x , x −1 ] Completion: k → ∞ Qp ↔ Fp ((x )). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
As in Shafaravich’s conjecture, one may consider Qp ⊂ Qp (µp∞ ) ⊂ Q̄p , or else ∞ Qp ⊂ Qp (p1/p ) ⊂ Q̄p , and complete p-adically: ∞ ∞ K := Qp (p1/p )ˆ ↔ K [ := Fp ((x 1/p )). The bijection between these two fields still does not preserve algebraic structure, but GK ∼= GK [ , (Fontaine, Wintenberger): the theory of algebraic equations over K is equivalent to the theory of algebraic equations over K [ (which is simpler: additions are carried out without carrying). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
This is the starting point of Scholze’s perfectoid geometry (2010; in his language, K and its tilt K [ are perfectoid fields), who established a tilting equivalence between perfectoid spaces over K and perfectoid spaces over K [ . This was the beginning of a new spring in Number Theory - not only toward the future of the theory, but also toward solving old questions from the 60’s in commutative algebra and algebraic geometry. 2 Moral of the story: introducing deep ramification (the p1/p , p1/p , etc.), instead of superficially complicating the situation, simplifies it dramatically. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
III.3. A different (and final) question: could one extend the absolute Galois theory of algebraic numbers to some transcendental numbers? Back to Euler: x sin x Πn∈Zr0 (1 − )= ∈ Q[[x ]], nπ x which suggests that the non-zero integral multiple of π may be considered as conjugates of π . If one insists to have a Galois group which permutes transitively the conjugates, one is forced to include all non-zero rational multiple of π as well. Whence a tentative answer: the Galois group is Q× and permutes the conjugates Q× .π . logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
Beyond zeta values, Euler also introduced multiple zeta values n1−s1 . . . nk−sk X ζ(s) = n1 >...>nk (in special cases), and discovered many algebraic relations between these numbers. X Zs = Q.ζ(s). s1 +...+sk =s These and other relations (discovered later) imply dimQ Zs 6 ds where ds are the Taylor coefficients of (1 − x 2 − x 3 )−1 , given by a Fibonacci-like recursion (Goncharov, Terasoma). One conjectures equality (Zagier). logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
The natural framework to discuss and prove this is the theory of motives: this was dreamed by Grothendieck in the 60’s, transformed into a useful fiction by Deligne in the mid 70’s, and then into a full-fledged theory by Voevodsky and others in the 90’s. To motives, one knows how to attach motivic Galois groups (a far reaching extension of Galois theory to systems of polynomials equations in several variables). For the motives attached to multiple zeta values, which are called mixed Tate motives over Z, their absolute Galois group - named the cosmic Galois group by Cartier because this group also controls renormalization theory of quantum fields - has been determined by Brown: it is an extension of Q∗ by a free (prounipotent) group. It would then follow from a deep conjecture in transcendental number theory (also due to Grothendieck) that this cosmic Galois group is the symmetry group of the multiple zeta values. logoslides Yves André - Paris Sorbonne, CNRS Storie dell’infinito aritmetico
You can also read