50 SHADES OF CONSENT: RE-DEFINING THE LAW'S TREATMENT OF SADOMASOCHISM
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 50 SHADES OF CONSENT: RE-DEFINING THE LAW’S TREATMENT OF SADOMASOCHISM INTRODUCTION In the spring of 2012, former NFL linebacker Junior Seau committed suicide as a result of repeated blows to the head during his career as a football player.1 Medical experts reveal the cause of the suicide was chronic traumatic encephalopathy (C.T.E.), a degenerative brain disease widely attributed to athletes who have absorbed ongoing blows.2 In light of the grave harm suffered by Seau and many other players, the Government has stepped in to fund and conduct research about this disease.3 Alternatively, consider a case where two homosexual adult partners engaged in a sadomasochistic relationship—one where expressions of intimacy coalesce with expressions of violence. After a consensual interaction in which the “Master” used a whip on his partner in the course of their mutually desired sexual encounter, the “Master” soon became a perpetrator in a criminal proceeding and received a sentence of 8 to 10 years for assault and battery with a deadly weapon.4 In both scenarios, the government clearly recognizes the need to regulate injuries sustained from violence. However, a question remains: Why doesn’t the government criminally prosecute Seau’s opposing players or the NFL for orchestrating the beatings that led to his death? The answer is that the law has carved an exception to sports-related injuries 1. Mary Pilon and Ken Bilson, Seau Suffered from Brain Disease: THE N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 10, 2013, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/11/sports/football/junior-seau-suffered- from-brain-disease.html?pagewanted=1&_r=0&hp. 2. Id. The article notes that “[s]ince C.T.E. was diagnosed in the brain of the former Eagles defensive back Andre Waters after his suicide in 2006, the disease has been found in nearly every former player whose brain was examined posthumously.” 3. Id. 4. Commonwealth v. Appleby, 402 N.E.2d 1051, 1053 (Mass. 1980). 97
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 98 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 notwithstanding the inherent danger in many contact sports. Conversely, the law traditionally has not provided similar protections for “deviant” or “kinky” sexual practices such as sadomasochism because it views these acts as socially undesirable. However, in the recent U.S. Supreme Court case, Lawrence v. Texas, the Court banned states from criminalizing sodomy between two consenting homosexual adults.5 The opinion truly underscores the importance of sexual and individual autonomy but leaves the legality of sadomasochism unanswered. Thus, this Comment proposes that sadomasochism (“S/M”) cases should be de-criminalized and re-analyzed through a civil framework of tort and contract theory in order to provide more protection for the privacy interests that Lawrence guarantees. This framework would be feasible for three reasons: First, S/M fits within Lawrence’s protective scope since criminal law’s artificial construction of an “injury” is arbitrarily applied to consensual S/M practices. Second, regulations based in tort and contract law would not only respect and uphold the privacy rights articulated in Lawrence, but the doctrines echo criminal law in ways that would preserve each body of law’s underlying “social harm” rationale wherever an act is deemed nonconsensual. Third, recent courts have effectively employed an analytical scheme based in tort and contract law, thereby implicitly recognizing the need for adaptation in this area of law. I. CRIMINAL LAW EXPOSED IN AN S/M CONTEXT A. Background As a general matter, an individual may not consent to injury incurred in the practice of S/M.6 The underlying rationale is that the principal injury caused by this conduct is the “crime” suffered by the public.7 Thus, even when an individual redresses his injury through private action, the state nonetheless has a great interest in punishing a party for the wrongful act itself. It has been stated that “the only true consent to a criminal act is that of the community,”8 because even if the harm occurred in private, such an 5. Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003). 6. States differ as to the level of injury to which an individual may consent, but the proscribed level of injury is generally deemed “serious.” MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.11 (1962). 7. WAYNE R. LAFAVE, SUBSTANTIVE CRIMINAL LAW § 6.5, at 59 (2d. ed. 2003). Consequences: significance of consent, conduct, or condonation by victim. 8. State v. Brown, 364 A.2d 27, 29 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1976).
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 99 act has an impingement upon the community and the very doing of the act may tend to encourage repetition and undermine public morals.9 This public harm rationale poses a substantial wrinkle for legal analysis in the face of Lawrence. In the handbook on the Law of Torts, leading tort scholar W. Page Keeton laments criminal law’s limitations when “the interest of the public is thrown into the scales and allowed to swing the balance for or against the plaintiff, the result is a form of ‘social engineering.’ A decisionmaker might deliberately seek to use the law as an instrument to promote the ‘greatest happiness of the greatest number’ or instead might give greater emphasis to protecting certain types of interests of individuals as fundamental entitlements central to an integrity of person that the law upholds above all else.”10 Given its utilitarian policy, criminal law alone as an analytical device for S/M cannot adequately comport with the Lawrence decision. B. Modified Approach To S/M & Harm The Lawrence decision undermines criminal law’s approach to S/M since this approach fails to align the treatment of S/M with that of other legally permissible practices including violent sports and body modification. As a general matter, courts tend to frown on S/M for its immoral undertones, even though Lawrence expressly proscribes such reprehension based on moral judgment.11 Courts’ failure to adequately explain why other dangerous practices like contact sports or body modification are legally acceptable, while S/M remains legally confined, suggests that courts use criminal law as a tool to artificially construe any S/M act as an assault. As a result, courts deprive S/M practitioners of their Lawrence protections of personal autonomy that other similarly situated parties receive.12 In Lawrence, its landmark opinion banning states from criminalizing sodomy between consenting adults, the Supreme Court noted that “[t]he issue is whether the majority may use the power of the State to enforce [their] views on the whole society through operation of criminal law. ‘Our obligation is to define the liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral 9. Id. 10. W. PAGE KEETON ET AL., PROSSER AND KEETON ON THE LAW OF TORTS 16 (5th ed. 1984). 11. See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 571. 12. Some activities that fall under Lawrence’s protective scope include: boxing, mixed martial arts, football and cosmetic surgery; See Kathy Sisson, The Cultural Formation of S/M in SAFE, SANE AND CONSENSUAL: CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON SADOMASOCHISM 10, 23 (Darren Langdridge & Meg Barker eds., 2007).
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 100 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 code.’”13 Ultimately, this decision exposes criminal law’s shortcomings in the context of S/M because according to Lawrence, “at the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.”14 Many S/M advocates would read this statement to include their right to engage in safe and private S/M conduct without fear of government intrusion since S/M is an expression of sexual autonomy.15 Under Lawrence, this pro-S/M argument would likely succeed but for the element of violence inherent in S/M. That physical harm is the crux of S/M immediately places S/M cases within the scope of criminal law with no legal recognition of a consent defense.16 On the one hand, opponents to S/M correctly point out that two individuals cannot consent or agree to commit a crime, which amounts to a contravention of public policy.17 On the other hand, proponents argue that S/M is not a crime at all but rather an expression of personal autonomy and that the flagrant moral disapproval targeted at S/M comes sharply into focus when S/M is compared to the physical incursions permitted in violent sports and body modification including piercings, tattoos, scarification, splitting, branding, and cosmetic surgery.18 13. Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 571 (quoting Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 850 (1992)). 14. Id. at 574. 15. See NATIONAL COALITION FOR SEXUAL FREEDOM, When the Levee Breaks: A guide to dealing with and avoiding arrest and prosecution in BDSM scenes (2012), https://ncsfreedom.org/images/stories/pdfs/Consent%20Counts/CC%20Doc/NCSF_Levee_21feb1 2_WEB.pdf; NATIONAL COALITION FOR SEXUAL FREEDOM, Consent Counts Program Description, A FEW RAYS OF HOPE available at https://ncsfreedom.org/key-programs/consent- counts/consent-counts/item/580-consent-and-bdsm-the-state-of-the-law.html (explaining that “the U.S. Supreme Court has created a doctrine of privacy that, at least in some areas of sexual behavior, now insulates consenting couples from criminal prosecution. While the doctrine of Lawrence v. Texas has not been applied in the BDSM context, the principle of privacy is a powerful one that works in our favor”). 16. See MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.11. 17. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 178 (1979). 18. Kelly Egan, Morality-Based Legislation is Alive and Well: Why the law permits consent to body modification but not sadomasochistic sex, 70 ALB. L. REV 1615, 1642 nn.3 & 100 (“Glans splitting” refers to splitting the head of the penis); See, e.g., R.M. Schneiderman, Cut-Prone Fighters Turn to Surgery to Limit Bleeding, N.Y. TIMES (July 10, 2009), available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/07/11/sports/11surgery.html?ref=mixedmartialarts&_r=0 (discussing plastic surgery procedures Mixed Martial Arts participants undergo, “Since at least the 1970s, boxers have had plastic surgeries to repair scar tissue and prevent excessive bleeding. But mixed martial arts, which combines wrestling, kickboxing and grappling, has a higher incidence of deep, potentially fight-ending lacerations, according to doctors who are familiar with both sports.”). This example has two levels of body-alterations: the mutilation associated with the actual fighting and the subsequent reconstructive surgeries to prevent excessive bleeding during the violent matches.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 101 While body modification does not rise to the same level of acceptance as sports, it nevertheless receives more legal protection than S/M does, despite the physical harm involved in both practices including risk of infections and complications.19 Proponents of body modification would argue that its social value comes from personal autonomy and self- expression.20 While S/M practitioners draw support from this same argument, courts presiding over S/M cases nonetheless tend to reject this argument, perhaps as a conscious (or even subconscious) way to denounce the practice itself. For instance, in several S/M cases, courts often exaggerate the seriousness of the injuries to condemn deviant sexual acts.21 In one S/M case, the court described the victim as having sustained “a swollen lip, large welts on her ankles, wrists, hips, buttocks, and severe bruises on her thighs”22—injuries that resemble the immediate markings of those who undergo reconstructive or plastic surgeries—yet the court’s deliberate and descriptive language suggests violence.23 Often, the difference between the actual harm sustained in an S/M setting and that incurred in a plastic surgery or tattooing procedure will be negligible, yet the S/M practitioner is subject to criminal prosecution while the plastic surgeon or tattoo artist is not. Thus, a comparison of the legal treatment of S/M with that of body modification and other permissible physical injuries exemplifies criminal law’s arbitrary definition of “harm.” C. S/M: Sex or Violence? This arbitrary notion of “harm” imposed on S/M is even more apparent through courts’ assumption that any violence in an S/M scene practiced in the privacy of one’s home is tantamount to assault. This misguided assumption in turn invalidates a consent defense since courts routinely conclude that no reasonable person would actually consent to violence during sex.24 Thus, since the law conceptualizes S/M as pure violence rather than sex, and violence is charged as an assault, S/M 19. Egan, supra note 18, at 1638-39 (noting that regulations for body modification have been minimal despite the risk of complications or injury); id. at n.3. 20. Id. at 1639. 21. Vera Bergelson, Consent to Harm, 28 PACE L. REV. 683, 691 (2008). 22. State v. Collier, 372 N.W.2d. 303, 304 (Iowa Ct. App. 1985); Bergelson, supra note 21, at 692. 23. Interview with Douglas M. Freedman, M.D., Orthopedic Surgeon associated with St. John’s Health Center in Santa Monica, Cal. (Mar. 13, 2013) (noting that “typical immediate findings after plastic surgery (and many surgeries) are bruising and swelling”). 24. See Govan v. State, 913 N.E.2d 237, 242-43 (Ind. Ct. App. 2009); see also State v. Guinn, Nos. 23886-1-II, 25856-1-II, 2001 Wash. App. LEXIS 502 at *11-*12.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 102 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 practitioners/defendants cannot even raise a consent defense.25 S/M practitioners argue that the exercise itself is not about hurting another person but it aims to provide pleasure through inflicting some pain and discomfort.26 In other words, since private S/M conduct is arguably commensurate with other sexual activities like sodomy, courts’ legal construction of S/M as assault is purely speculative and in need of reconsideration.27 Despite the language in Lawrence limiting its protections to situations that are free from injury or coercion,28 unfairly narrow interpretations of its holding fail to consider the key argument advanced by S/M advocates: that S/M is sex.29 As such, a re-conceptualized notion of S/M as private sexual conduct would transform a charge of assault into one of battery involving sexual overtones where courts do allow a consent defense.30 Thus far, however, courts have been reluctant to categorize S/M activity as the “sexual overtone” element in a battery charge and consequently courts view S/M as strictly an assault barring any consent defense. This arbitrary imposition that S/M can only be an assault “undermines the ability of practitioners to define their own pleasure”31 and the right to define “one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.”32 A recent S/M case in Indiana reaffirmed the general rule that consent is ordinarily a defense to a charge of battery when the conduct involves sexual overtones.33 However, the court concluded that the presence of a deadly weapon, namely a knife, used in the sexual encounter between defendant 25. See supra note 6 and accompanying text; see also Monica Pa, Beyond the Pleasure Principle: The Criminalization of Consensual Sadomasochistic Sex, 11 TEX. J. WOMEN & L. 51, 77 (2001); LISA ANNE ZILNEY & LAURA J. ZILNEY, RECONSIDERING SEX CRIMES AND OFFENDERS: PROSECUTION OR PERSECUTION? 82 (2009). 26. ZILNEY & ZILNEY, supra note 25, at 82. 27. See, e.g., Lawrence, 539 U.S at 582-83. 28. See id. at 578. 29. See ZILNEY & ZILNEY, supra note 25, at 82; Matt Haber, A Hush-Hush Topic No More, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 27, 2013, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2013/02/28/fashion/bondage- domination-and-kink-sex-communities-step-into-view.html?pagewanted=all (noting that domestic violence and dominance/submission are entirely different); Charles Moser and Peggy J. Kleinplatz, Themes of SM Expression in SAFE, SANE, AND CONSENSUAL: CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON SADOMASOCHISM 35, 45 (Darren Langdridge & Meg Barker eds., 2007) (explaining that despite the common assumption that S/M is abusive, most S/M practitioners do not consider the experience as “painful” and instead consider it a desired “intensity” of sexual arousal). 30. Govan, 913 N.E.2d at 242. 31. See Pa, supra note 25, at 79. 32. Lawrence, 539 U.S at 574. 33. Govan, 913 N.E.2d at 242.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 103 and victim precluded consent as a defense.34 This case illustrates the challenge that S/M practitioners face: the presence of violent expressions and/or paraphernalia automatically transforms what sadomasochists call “sex” into “assault” presumably because courts find it inconceivable (if not abhorrent) that individuals would elect to use weapons during sex and therefore, as a matter of law, a consent defense should not even be available in this context. In another case, the defendant solicited sex from prostitutes, and he proceeded to assault, rape and sodomize the women after taking them into a deserted shack and holding a gun to their head and a knife to their throat.35 He was charged with five counts of first degree rape, five counts of second degree assault, four counts of first degree kidnapping and three counts of first degree robbery.36 He argued that all of the women, but one, consented to participate in this sadomasochistic activity including shaving their pubic hair, pouring hot wax on various parts of their bodies, putting safety pins in their nipples and foreign objects in their rectums.37 He claimed that the women accused him of rape when he failed to pay them for their services.38 The appellate court held that there was no abuse in discretion in the trial court’s excluding expert testimony which could explain how sexually deviant activities like S/M can be consensual.39 The court reasoned that such testimony would have minimal assistance to the jury: That some people may consent to sadomasochistic acts has little bearing on whether these victims did. Moreover, the issue of consent turns not so much upon sadomasochistic practices as upon the entire course of events, including taking the victims to deserted places, controlling them with a gun, tying and taping them, and threatening to kill them. Jurors did not need expert testimony to decide whether, under these circumstances, the 40 victim consented. Apparently, the court assumed that “physical pain” satisfied the “physical injury” element, and under this logic, naturally any S/M conduct may be characterized as assault.41 In the foregoing examples, regardless of whether the courts reached a “correct” conclusion as to the subject conduct, the problematic issue is that the possibility of consent was never a 34. Id. at 242-43. 35. State v. Guinn, Nos. 23886-1-II, 25856-1-II, 2001 Wash. App. LEXIS 502 at *2-5. 36. Id. at *5-6. 37. Id. at *2-7. 38. Id. at *6. 39. Id. at *11. 40. Id. at *12 (emphasis omitted). 41. See id. at *34; Bergelson, supra note 21, at 692.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 104 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 consideration for the trier of fact. What Govan and Guinn illustrate is that the rule of consent is arbitrary and strict and notably unavailable in certain contexts.42 People may only consent to an activity if it is on a list of things the state approves, “but the law envisions no balancing or accommodation of conflicting interests of an individual and society. The disregard for an individual, inherent in this rule, goes against the basic principles of autonomy and personal responsibility defining American criminal law.”43 Thus, for an S/M practitioner to use Lawrence effectively as a shield from criminal liability, courts must first re-characterize S/M as a form of private and consensual sexual conduct rather than mere injury or coercion.44 Ultimately, a consent defense will not automatically condone all sexual practices or excuse the perpetrators of violence from criminal liability by merely raising such a defense. Rather, the critical issue is that the defense is categorically unavailable in many cases where an individual is (or at least should be) entitled to the rights and protections provided by Lawrence. D. Re-conceptualizing S/M under Lawrence Drawing on a more modern and liberal social understanding of S/M as sex, rather than pure violence, S/M activists have argued that S/M practitioners should fall within Lawrence’s protective ambit.45 One important development in S/M activism is the forthcoming amendment to the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM), which will depathologize sadism and masochism in its upcoming edition.46 As such, the American Psychiatric Association’s Paraphilias Subworkgroup’s DSM revisions acknowledge that individuals can be fetishists and sexual sadists or masochists without having a mental disorder.47 Even the most recent edition of the DSM changed the criteria for S/M preferences to diagnose these sexual urges or fetishes as mental disorders only if “‘the 42. See Guinn, 2001 Wash. App. LEXIS 502 at *11; see also Govan v. State, 913 N.E.2d 237, 242 (Ind. Ct. App. 2009); Bergelson, supra note 21, at 693. 43. Bergelson, supra note 21, at 693. 44. Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578 (2003). 45. NATIONAL COALITION FOR SEXUAL FREEDOM, supra note 15. Aside from the legal issue of consent, there is a changing social climate with respect to S/M and the current case law and treatment of S/M does not fit with modern understandings of this practice. While maybe S/M is not for everyone, proponents argue that practitioners should at least be given the option to fully present their case. 46. NATIONAL COALITION FOR SEXUAL FREEDOM, Kinky is Not a Diagnosis (Feb. 16, 2010), https://ncsfreedom.org/key-programs/dsm-v-revision-project/kinky-is-not-a-diagnosis.html 47. Id.; Cf. Moser and Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 60 (“[S]ports injuries are far more likely to lead to emergency room visits but weekend athletes are not automatically diagnosed with mental disorders.”).
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 105 behaviors cause clinically significant distress or impairment in social occupational or other important areas of functioning,” or in the case of sadism ‘if [t]he person has acted on these sexual urges with a nonconsenting person.’”48 The changes to the DSM undoubtedly reflect a greater acceptance for S/M and other alternative sex practices over the decades.49 For instance, studies indicate that the overwhelming majority of people who engage in S/M are individuals who are normal, healthy and contributing to society.50 Scientist Ronald Moglia claims that S/M is most popular among educated, upper and middle class individuals, and that people of all races and creeds practice S/M.51 The Kinsey Institute New Report on Sex estimated that most individuals experiment with a mild form of S/M including spanking or blindfolding.52 Research reveals that sexual arousal from S/M-related activities is not rare and that an average of 5-10% of the U.S. population engages in some form of S/M sex.53 Furthermore, the DSM’s history of pathologizing now commonplace and accepted sexual urges and behaviors (like masturbation and homosexuality) calls into the question the reliability of its previous characterizations of S/M as “disorders.”54 As various “deviant” sexual practices have gone in and out of fashion, they have also gone in and out of psychiatric diagnosis suggesting that social norms implicitly dictate the criteria associated with sexual disorders.55 Additionally, psychiatrists note that any manifested dysfunction associated with S/M may come from the social stigma surrounding the practice, akin to an internalized homonegativity experienced by gay and lesbian individuals.56 The 48. Richard B. Krueger, The DSM Diagnostic Criteria for Sexual Masochism, AMERICAN PSYCHIATRIC ASSOCIATION (2010) at *3, http://www.dsm5.org/Research/Documents/Krueger_ ASB%20Feb%202011.pdf. The older DSM included a per se diagnosis that association with S/M alone was enough to be a mental disorder. Id.; Egan, supra note 18, at 1637; Moser and Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 57. 49. See Matt Haber, A Hush-Hush Topic No More, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 27, 2013, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2013/02/28/fashion/bondage-domination-and-kink-sex-communities- step-into-view.html?pagewanted=all. 50. Pa, supra note 25, at 60; see Moser and Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 56-59; see NATIONAL COALITION FOR SEXUAL FREEDOM, Kinky is Not a Diagnosis (Feb. 16, 2010), https://ncsfreedom.org/key-programs/dsm-v-revision-project/kinky-is-not-a-diagnosis.html. 51. Pa, supra note 25, at 60. 52. Moser & Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 56; Pa, supra note 25, at 59-60. 53. Moser & Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 56; Pa, supra note 25, at 59. 54. Moser and Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 56. 55. Id. 56. Id. at 57.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 106 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 recommended “treatment” therefore is to validate these sexual preferences rather than to suppress S/M desires altogether.57 Ultimately psychiatric research coupled with an increasing cultural acceptance of S/M and experimentation with kinky sex58 suggests that Lawrence should not be read too narrowly so as to exclude the possibility that forceful sex can actually be consensual and mutually satisfying.59 In addition, Lawrence explains the importance of respecting individual autonomy under the Fourteenth Amendment and that “at the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence.”60 Perhaps more modern social interpretations of S/M will alter the way the law treats S/M practitioners since many “demonstrate no more pathology than the general public”61 and the ability to chose “one’s own concept of existence”62 as espoused by Lawrence should include safe sadomasochistic practices. Ultimately, individuals who practice S/M safely and consensually are not very different than those participating in extremely violent athletics including mixed martial arts or body alteration—the key distinction is the latter group of activities enjoys the benefit of an exception to criminal liability.63 While opponents of S/M certainly have a valid fear that de- criminalization of S/M will create an easier defense for rapists and sexual 57. Id. 58. See Matt Haber, A Hush-Hush Topic No More, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 27, 2013, http:// www.nytimes.com/2013/02/28/fashion/bondage-domination-and-kink-sex-communities-step-into- view.html?pagewanted=all; NATIONAL COALITION FOR SEXUAL FREEDOM, 50 Shades PR: BDSM 50 Shades of Gray [sic] is a National Phenomenon (Mar. 4, 2012), https://ncsfreedom.org/ component/k2/item/693-50-shades-pr.html. Popular culture and media capture the growing interest in S/M and bondage. The curiosity of S/M includes the proliferation of sex toys, high fashion lines alluding to bondage and fetishism, S/M themed restaurants and hotels, films and literature. More recently, the erotic novel entitled Fifty Shades of Grey which depicts S/M scenes between two sophisticated young adults has become a cultural sensation introducing dominant/submissive sex play into the bedrooms of people ordinarily unfamiliar with S/M; see also Interview by The Cast of The View with E.L. James Author, Fifty Shades of Grey, N.Y. (May 11, 2012), available at http://www.tressugar.com/EL-James-View-23063732 (featuring interview with Fifty Shades of Grey author E.L. James and noting that she is responsible for many revitalized marriages); for a discussion of these modern S/M trends, see Sisson, supra note 12, at 18, 21 & 29. 59. See Haber, supra note 58. Dr. Charley Ferrer, a clinical psychologist in Manhattan and Staten Island and the author of “BDSM: The Naked Truth” notes that domestic violence is entirely different than submission/dominance within BDSM. Id. 60. Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 574 (2003) (quoting Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992)). 61. Egan, supra note 18, at 1637. 62. Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 574. 63. Assoc. Press, Connecticut Lifts Ban on Mixed Martial Arts Fights, NY TIMES (July 12, 2003), http://www.nytimes.com/2013/07/12/sports/connecticut-lifts-ban-on-fights.html?ref= mixedmartialarts&_r=0.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 107 abusers, Lawrence does not eliminate prosecution against actual sex offenders.64 Rather, Lawrence allows courts to protect private sexual behavior that does not pose a real risk of violence, although it may be at odds with societal norms. In other words, the essence of Lawrence as applied to S/M is that certain sexual practices that some may consider “abnormal” or “deviant” should not be criminalized per se. In an effort to protect the abuse of a consent defense, expert testimony could be used to educate the jury about S/M and how most S/M practitioners engage in careful negotiation before sex.65 An expert could also testify about the distinctive features of S/M that set it apart from domestic violence. Domestic violence involves behavioral patterns aimed to isolate the victim, and creates cycles of abuse and apologies.66 Unlike domestic violence, however, S/M partners ask for and enjoy the behavior and there is no apology for the behavior once it ends, both partners are satisfied that it occurred.67 II. UNSHACKLING CRIMINAL LAW: CONSENT, TORT AND CONTRACT THEORY A. Consent & Tort Law Redefining S/M as sex is only part of the solution. S/M—just like any other arrangement between parties—can go awry. To balance the need for sexual autonomy with the law’s need to protect the general public, a legal framework of tort and contract law could be employed to determine whether the alleged consent to certain conduct is in fact valid and/or reasonable. This analytical scheme would ensure that privacy interests are protected while simultaneously upholding public condemnation of egregious and unilateral acts of violence. In many ways tort law and criminal law are very similar since both bodies of law seek to secure persons against harm or physical interference and both have the purpose of establishing acceptable standards of conduct.68 The shared concern for public welfare is what unites tort law and criminal 64. See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578. 65. See discussion infra Part II. 66. Pa, supra note 25, at 87. 67. Id. 68. See KEETON ET AL., supra note 10, § 1, at 6-7; Susan Rose-Ackerman, Tort Law in the Regulatory State, in TORT LAW AND THE PUBLIC INTEREST 80, 80-81 (Peter Schuck ed., 1991).
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 108 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 law.69 Unlike contract law, which governs parties who have elected to be in a relationship, tort law governs individuals merely by virtue of their societal membership, similar to criminal law. Even though tort law applies to private actions between private parties with specific injuries and damages, it emulates criminal law by espousing social policy goals by deterring unreasonably risky conduct through shaping the behavior of individuals.70 Unlike criminal law, however, tort law adheres to the principle violenti non fit injuria meaning: to one who is willing, no wrong is done.71 Thus, under civil tort law, parties can use consent to negate the wrongfulness of an alleged tort. Professor Keeton explains that, “[o]ne, of course, consents to an invasion such as a sex contact if he or she wants or desires the invasion. Consent avoids recovery simply because it destroys the wrongfulness of the conduct as between consenting parties, however harmful it might be to the interest of others, and even though it is perhaps both immoral and criminal.”72 If this legal rationale were to apply to S/M, an S/M participant charged with assault would have the option of elucidating the facts and circumstances to the trier fact rather than that person being strictly liable under the current legal regime that equates sexual violence with criminality. Again, the point of a consent defense is not that it would give a “get out of jail free” card for any person who choses to assert that defense, but rather it would be a way to ensure that a party is guaranteed his constitutional right to a fair trial.73 As applied to S/M practitioners, the consent defense would simply give the defendant the right to explain his or her side of the story to the trier of fact. As tort cases illustrate, the issue of consent is a matter of fact, and the trier of fact is able to consider all the evidence before deciding whether there was valid consent. Moreover, a trier of fact can determine that consent should not be a defense to certain conduct if there is evidence that a party exceeded the scope of the actual consent given.74 B. Duty & Reasonableness Both courts of law and S/M practitioners incorporate tort law principles including duty, reasonableness, strict liability and assumption of risk into their respective understandings and treatment of S/M. For instance, 69. See KEETON ET AL., supra note 10, § 1, at 6-7; Rose-Ackerman, supra note 68. 70. See KEETON ET AL., supra note 10, § 1, at 6-7; Rose-Ackerman, supra note 68. 71. See KEETON ET AL., supra note 10, § 18, at 112. 72. Id. at 113. 73. U.S. CONST. amend. VI; U.S. CONST. amend. XIV, § 1. 74. KEETON ET AL., supra note 10, § 18, at 118.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 109 practitioners recognize that sadists and masochists owe a duty of care to one another and often have codes of conduct for their practices.75 In both tort and criminal law, the concept of “reasonableness” is critical. The notion of “reasonableness” is a permanent fixture in tort law on two levels. First, on an individual level, tort law assesses the reasonableness of conduct between individuals and second, at a societal level, it emphasizes the reasonableness of conduct as it applies to the public at large.76 For instance, echoing the principles of both tort and criminal law, one court noted that, “the public has an interest in the personal safety of its citizens and is injured where the safety of any individual is threatened, whether by himself or another.”77 In the criminal law context, however, at least as it pertains to S/M cases, courts often project a biased assessment of the “reasonableness” standard. For example, one court expressed its opinion that, “a normal person in full possession of his or her mental faculties does not freely consent to the use, upon himself, of force.”78 Clearly, this myopic interpretation is problematic since it plainly ignores violent and ultrahazardous activities. In other words, what makes violence unreasonable in an S/M context would not necessarily be unreasonable in another socially acceptable context like mixed martial arts or football.79 The inherently contradictory nature of S/M, urging safety and sanity80 on the part of participants, is a concept that many people, and indeed many courts find difficult to accept. Specifically, the fact that a masochist consents to and even derives pleasure from harm calls into question the existence of an injury, yet the fact that is often overlooked is that sadomasochists essentially tailor their personal notion of “reasonableness” to fit their needs. For instance, S/M activists insist fellow practitioners to be reasonable in their conduct in order to reduce injury, yet what a sadomasochist considers “reasonable” sexual conduct often does not comport with socially acceptable sexual practices.81 75. Sophia, Who Is in Charge in an SM Scene?, in SAFE, SANE, AND, CONSENSUAL: CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON SADOMASOCHISM 271, 274-275 (Darren Langdridge & Meg Barker eds., 2007). 76. See State v. Brown, 364 A.2d 27, 28 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1976). 77. Id. 78. People v. Samuels, 58 Cal. Rptr. 439, 447 (Ct. App. 1967). 79. See supra p.1 and text accompanying note 18. 80. See infra notes 84-87, 98 and accompanying text; see also Sophia, supra note 75, at 271. 81. See Pat Califia & Robin Sweeney, Safer-Sex Guidelines for Leatherdykes, in THE SECOND COMING: A LEATHERDYKE READER, 351, 351 (Pat Califia & Robin Sweeney eds., 1996).
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 110 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 While both courts of law and S/M practitioners espouse the principle that “reasonableness” should govern interpersonal interactions, the implicit standard of reasonableness that courts use in S/M cases only has room for the court’s concept of what constitutes reasonable behavior. According to one author writing about S/M, “the law limits women’s pursuit of pleasure through pain, thus prescribing normative behaviors that can be paternalistic and repressive. The current doctrine of consent assumes that no reasonable woman would or should consent to sexual activity that involves violent domination, just as it once assumed women had no right to play sports.”82 This assumption runs counter to the propositions set forth in Lawrence as S/M practitioners are at the whim of decision maker’s constructions of reasonableness. One reason that the concept of “reasonableness’ varies between S/M practitioners and the court is that the “reasonable person standard” does not entail the consideration of a “reasonable sadomasochist.” According to Professor Keeton, in tort law, the expected conduct from the reasonable person “will vary with the situation with which he is confronted…. [H]e is rather a personification of a community ideal of reasonable behavior, determined by the jury’s social judgment.”83 Thus, the traits of this fictional character include those of the actor whose conduct is being judged from an S/M practitioner’s standpoint who can bring some degree of personalized objectivity to an area that might be incomprehensible to an outsider. Furthermore, safety and sanity are paramount to the reasonable S/M practitioner who insists on exercising caution and informed consent prior to an S/M activity. S/M activists Pat Califia and Robin Sweeney contend that safe sex means being responsible for one’s conduct.84 While safety is a matter of degree, there are basic imperatives that practitioners expect of reasonable S/M participants including bringing one’s own sex toys to a sex party and making sure to avoid inflicting unwanted injury on a partner.85 82. Cheryl Hanna, Sex is Not a Sport: Consent and Violence in Criminal Law, 42 B.C. L. Rev. 239, 270 (2001). 83. KEETON ET AL., supra note 10, § 32, at 175 (footnotes omitted). Keeton notes that this fictitious character sometimes “is described as a reasonable person, or a person of ordinary prudence, or a person of reasonable prudence, or some other blend of reason and caution. It is evident that all such phrases are intended to mean very much the same thing. The actor is required to do what such an ideal individual would be supposed to do in his place. A model of all proper qualities, with only those human shortcomings and weaknesses which the community will tolerate on the occasion, ‘this excellent but odious character stands like a monument in our Courts of Justice, vainly appealing to his fellow-citizens to order their lives after his own example.’” Id. at 174 (footnotes omitted). 84. Califia & Sweeney, supra note 81, at 351. 85. See, e.g., Robin Sweeney, Sex Party Savoir Faire, in THE SECOND COMING: A LEATHERDYKE READER 187, 189-91 (Pat Califia & Robin Sweeney eds., 1996); Pat Califia, A
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 111 Sanity too is crucial for a reasonable sadist so that he or she can make informed decisions about activities to participate in.86 Ultimately then, it is from a modified reasonable person standard that the principles of safety and sanity87 are best communicated. In sum, the legal system should adopt a looser framework to assess S/M to provide for this flexible standard of reasonableness in an S/M context. After all, the notion of a “reasonable person standard” necessarily changes with the times, and in this post-Lawrence era, entails more of an open mind than courts seem to afford to that “reasonable person.” If courts were to broaden their analysis of reasonable conduct in accordance with the modern social climate, courts, in theory, would be able to minimize the possibility of excessive injury and exploitation as well as maintaining social control of citizenry. While there is no guarantee that such a framework would solve all problems, it is clear at this point that the current legal regime does not even attempt the balancing act that Lawrence demands. C. Contract Law In addition to tort law, contract theory would be a viable legal device for S/M analysis as many modern S/M practitioners enter into a contract prior to an S/M scene to carefully delineate acceptable and prohibited acts.88 E L James’ book, Fifty Shades of Grey, highlights this negotiating practice in a fictional setting,89 but importantly, it reflects changing social values that criminal law is apparently ill-equipped to address.90 As such, to bridge the gap between contract law and criminal law, the legal system must have a modern understanding of what S/M entails. House Divided: Violence in the Lesbian S/M Community, in THE SECOND COMING: A LEATHERDYKE READER 264, 271-72 (Pat Califia & Robin Sweeney eds., 1996). 86. See Lisa Downing, Beyond Safety: Erotic Asphyxiation and the Limits of SM Discourse, in SAFE, SANE, AND, CONSENSUAL: CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES ON SADOMASOCHISM 119, 120 (Darren Langdridge & Meg Barker eds., 2007). 87. See id. 88. Lamar Van Dyke, Contracts and Contract Negotiating, in THE SECOND COMING: A LEATHERDYKE READER 205, 208-19 (Pat Califia & Robin Sweeney eds., 1996). 89. EL James’ character, Christian Grey, “the Dominant,” requires his “Submissive,” Anastasia, to sign an agreement before engaging in any S/M activity: “HARD LIMITS: No acts involving fire play, no acts involving urination or defecation and the products thereof. No acts involving needles, knives, piercing, or blood.” E L JAMES, FIFTY SHADES OF GREY 107 (2011). 90. Fifty Shades of Grey has cultivated a massive following and has become one of the fastest-selling paperbacks of all time. Earlier in 1954, The Story of O, another erotic, S/M themed novel gained a huge following as well. These cultural sensations reflect society’s growing interest and acceptance with alternative sex practices; ultimately they suggest that notions of what constitutes sex change over time.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 112 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 The main distinction between criminal law and contract law is that contract theory protects private interests and criminal law preserves social order. The policy behind contract law implicates notions of liberty and self- determination that the Constitution recognizes in its Contract Clause.91 Thus, contract doctrine is a useful analytical device to appreciate the agency of two consenting parties in an S/M arrangement. More narrowly in the S/M context, contract law can be closely related to criminal law with respect to mutual assent, consideration, interpretation and breach as these principles set the foundation for whether a valid agreement existed in the first place, and whether a party violated the agreement. In other words, these concepts help determine whether the participants to an S/M encounter truly agreed to the conduct that actually took place, in the same way a showing of valid consent may preclude criminal liability in a sexual assault case. Yet, in the current legal regime governing S/M that finds it roots in criminal law rather than contract law, courts are clear that evidence of consent will not preclude criminal liability.92 Further, parties cannot contract to commit acts that violate public policy considerations like agreeing to commit serious crimes.93 However, a post-Lawrence interpretation of sexual autonomy and liberty suggest that the practice of S/M at least deserves to be examined through a contractual lens in order to fully understand the parties’ rights at stake. Accordingly, supporters of S/M frame their arguments under the policy of contractual freedom.94 Furthermore, various S/M advocate groups have formed over time such as the Eulenspiegal Society and the Society of Janus—two of the largest S/M organizations within the U.S.95 Within these groups is a consistent community slogan: “safe, sane and consensual.”96 These organizations insist on self-regulation within the community due to their lack of legal recognition by establishing standards of conduct in accordance with the credo “safe, sane and consensual”—with special emphasis on the “consensual” element.97 The principles embedded in this slogan recommend that S/M be practiced in such a manner: (1) to identify and prevent health 91. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 10, cl. 1. 92. See, e.g. MODEL PENAL CODE § 2.11(2) (Official Draft and Revised Comments 1985). 93. See, e.g. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 178 (1979). 94. See Moser & Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 35 (noting that contractual parties may, themselves, have different views of what constitutes S/M, making “self-definition” of boundaries crucial); Van Dyke, supra note 88, at 208-19 (discussing various S/M contract types and strategies for contract negotiation). 95. Sisson, supra note 12, at 18. 96. Id. at 23. 97. Downing, supra note 86, at 120-127.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 113 risks (“safe”); (2) to engage in activities in a rational state of mind (“sane”); and (3) to ensure that all the activities are agreed upon by the parties involved (“consensual”).98 Within S/M discourse, advocates routinely emphasize the “consensual” component and how mutuality of definition and negotiation is extremely important for building trust in an S/M relationship.99 Therefore, contract doctrine would be a particularly effective framework for S/M analysis since the principles underlying contract law would enable S/M practitioners to create a workable agreement, and the enforceability of this agreement might be given more weight in light of Lawrence. Ultimately, if contract law were to be included in the legal analysis of S/M, the law would more effectively regulate the practice in accordance with the values and regulations that S/M practitioners themselves esteem. D. Mutual Assent, Certainty of Terms & Consideration As a starting point, S/M practitioners encourage a “meeting of the minds” or mutual assent where both parties must intend to engage in S/M activities and must agree on the main terms of the agreement.100 Califia claims that an S/M relationship is successful when both parties negotiate and reach a comfortable agreement.101 This contractual arrangement incorporates the contract principles mutual assent and intent to be bound whereby the top and bottom decide how they will “play,” what is likely to occur and the duration of the scene.102 Another prominent S/M activist, Lamar Van Dyke, also recognizes the importance in negotiating a scene beforehand when she stresses that the parties bound to an agreement have tremendous responsibility for a situation that should not be taken lightly.103 An S/M practitioner even noted that “the presence of violence enhances the amount of trust we have for one another, and how important it is to trust your partner that he will not hurt you more than what you’ve asked for.”104 98. Id. 99. Moser & Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 38 (asserting that “SM is consensual by definition . . . [T]he difference between SM and violence is consent”); Sophia, supra note 75, at 272 (“Negotiation, whether open or hidden, is the key to successful consensual BDSM.”). 100. See sources cited supra note 99; see also RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 17 (1979). 101. PAT CALIFIA, PUBLIC SEX: THE CULTURE OF RADICAL SEX 171 (2nd ed. 2000). 102. Id. 103. Van Dyke, supra note 88, at 211. 104. Interview with an Anonymous S/M practitioner in L.A., Cal. (Jan. 15, 2013); see Sophia, supra note 75, at 272 (discussing the negotiated power exchange between S/M partners and how an interaction will fluctuate based on the level of trust between the parties).
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 114 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 In contract law, the “certainty of terms” doctrine ensures that both parties manifest their assent to a bargain in a way that is sufficiently definite and certain in order to determine whether a breach exists.105 As applied to S/M communities, this doctrine guides practitioners by reinforcing the importance of defining the terms of the contract such that a breach will be readily apparent when a partner strays from the terms within the agreement. Specifically, the S/M community seriously frowns upon transgressions of the limits that parties set in their agreement—this conduct resembles a breach of contract.106 Thus, contractual negotiation within the S/M community is of heightened importance as activists routinely encourage practitioners to try to cover everything they [practitioners] are thinking about, and not to make any assumptions, but to keep things clear.107 In addition to mutual assent and certainty of terms, a valid contract is comprised of a bargained for exchange which requires mutuality of obligation, also known as consideration.108 Within the S/M scheme, consideration relates to the pain inflicted and simultaneous pleasure that is derived from S/M acts. Pat Califia observes that, “S/M relationships are usually egalitarian” and the shared pleasure results in intense sensations for both parties.109 Furthermore, the consideration element distinguishes fair and mutually satisfying S/M play from unwanted sex because when an act resembles assault this conduct is no longer part of the bargained for exchange. Finally, S/M practitioners and advocates even recommend that parties draft a written contract prior to engaging in an S/M scene so that the terms of the agreement are spelled out.110 Activist Van Dyke even offers a boilerplate form for a Thirty-Day Consensual Slave Contract that reads: “I, ________,do hereby willingly and consensually agree to serve as slave to ____________for a period of thirty days . . . I agree to turn my body, mind, and spirit over to the Boss Lady to do with as she pleases.”111 Van Dyke underscores the importance of having a written agreement based on her personal experience. She notes, When I began to put things in writing, it seemed to help clarify exactly where I was at. When others found themselves engaging in dialogue prior to signing a piece of paper, they took it more seriously . . . [w]e could both 105. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 33 (1979). 106. Moser & Kleinplatz, supra note 29, at 37-38; see also Sophia, supra note 75, at 273. 107. Van Dyke, supra note 88, at 208. 108. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 71 (1979). 109. CALIFIA, supra note 101, at 172. 110. Van Dyke, supra note 88, at 214-15. 111. Id. at 215.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 2013] 5 0 S HAD ES O F CO NS E N T 115 refer to it when we needed to. There could be no mistaken intentions. Our 112 agreement was clear. E. Tort and Contract Law applied to S/M Case Law In 1980, the court found consent to battery immaterial in Commonwealth v. Appleby,113 (hereinafter referred to as “Appleby”), an S/M case where the defendant’s use of a riding crop was sufficient for purposes of finding the use of a dangerous weapon.114 The court stated that the law need not wait until the instrument actually does cause serious bodily injury, and that any touching with a potentially dangerous weapon can satisfy assault and battery by means of a dangerous weapon under Massachusetts criminal statutes.115 However, had the case been analyzed under the umbrella of tort and contract law, the defendant’s consent argument might at least have mitigated his liability under the backdrop of Lawrence where sexual freedom and privacy is conferred to consenting adults. In Appleby, the complaining witness and his testimony that the “[defendant] was going a little over what [the witness] was used to”116 would still be a valid defense that the defendant either exceeded consent, breached his duty of care or went outside the terms of the agreement. The Supreme Court of Massachusetts in Appleby even recognized the disproportionately extreme sentence Appleby received of 8 to 10 years since no physical injury resulted and the assault consisted of a riding crop blow that just barely connected with the witness’ back.117 The court noted: “[W]e express some reservation on the severity of the sentence imposed for the particular assault and battery on August 31, 1976, as established by the jury verdict . . . [but] that subject is not open to review by this tribunal.”118 Additionally, the concurrence recognized this concern too by stating that since the injury was very minor the sentence was likely influenced by “certain related circumstances which are abhorrent to most persons.”119 The tacit recognition of consent in Appleby suggests that courts are aware that a strict criminal law analysis has deficiencies. For instance, People v. Samuels was the first case to hold that a victim’s consent to S/M 112. Id. at 208. 113. Commonwealth v. Appleby, 402 N.E.2d 1051, 1060-61 (Mass. 1980). 114. Id. at 1058. The court noted that “the riding crop never caused ‘welts,’ but only ‘redness,’ in fact none of the beatings caused more than ‘redness.’” Id. at 1056. 115. Id. at 1058. 116. Id. at 1054. 117. Id. 118. Id. at 1061 119. Id. at 1062.
3.MEEPOS.ARTICLE.MACRO (DO NOT DELETE) 3/7/2014 1:30 PM 116 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 43 is not a valid defense to assault.120 The defendant in this case made violent sadomasochistic themed movies, and contended that the alleged victim consented since he was merely acting for the role.121 Hypothetically under tort theory, the analysis could have shifted to allow for an assumption of risk defense. In this case, law enforcement officers were unable to locate the complainant but in his absence the court nonetheless reasoned that “[i]t is a matter of common knowledge that a normal person in full possession of his mental faculties does not freely consent to the use, upon himself, of force likely to produce great bodily injury.”122 Again, this notion fails to account for ultrahazardous activities that fall within the protective scope of the assumption of risk doctrine. Ultimately, the court restricted an assumption of risk approach by looking at the public policy underlying this defense: that assumption of risk cannot go so far as to defeat the fundamental purpose of statutes enacted for the actor’s benefit.123 In State v. Collier, the court evaluated the “reasonableness” of S/M itself and ultimately confined its reasoning to pre-Lawrence assumptions about morality.124 The court balanced the social utility of S/M with the likelihood of harm and found that “[w]hatever rights the defendant may enjoy regarding private sexual activity, when such activity results in the whipping or beating of another resulting in bodily injury, such rights are outweighed by the State’s interest in protecting its citizens’ health, safety, and moral welfare.”125 This superficial negligence analysis reveals that courts tend to exaggerate the seriousness of factors “in order to condemn an unwanted activity.”126 Thus, the court here seemed to tailor its evaluation of reasonableness to preserve community values threatened by S/M conduct. The court noted that, “to allow an otherwise criminal act to go unpunished because of a victim’s consent would not only threaten the security of 120. People v. Samuels, 58 Cal. Rptr. 439, 447 (Ct. App. 1967). 121. Id. at 443-47. 122. Id. at 447. 123. The Samuels court reasoned that “[e]ven if it be assumed that the victim in the ‘vertical’ film did in fact suffer from some mental aberration which compelled him to submit to a beating which was so severe as to constitute an aggravated assault, defendant’s conduct in inflicting that beating was no less violative of a penal statute obviously designed to prohibit one human being from severely or mortally injuring another.” Id. Again, this argument improperly suggests that S/M practitioners not only have “mental aberrations” but that the presence of violence during sex can be nothing more than assault. 124. State v. Collier, 372 N.W.2d 303, 307 (Iowa Ct. App. 1985). 125. Id. at 307 (“[I]t is obvious to this court that the legislature did not intend the term to include an activity which has been repeatedly disapproved by other jurisdictions and considered to be in conflict with the general moral principles of our society.”). 126. Vera Bergelson, The Right to Be Hurt: Testing the Boundaries of Consent, 75 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 165, 179 (2007).
You can also read