Trans Fat Bans and Human Freedom - David Resnik, National Institutes of Health
←
→
Page content transcription
If your browser does not render page correctly, please read the page content below
The American Journal of Bioethics, 10(3): 27–32, 2010 ISSN: 1526-5161 print / 1536-0075 online DOI: 10.1080/15265160903585636 Target Article Trans Fat Bans and Human Freedom David Resnik, National Institutes of Health A growing body of evidence has linked consumption of trans fatty acids to cardiovascular disease. To promote public health, numerous state and local governments in the United States have banned the use of artificial trans fats in restaurant foods, and additional bans may follow. Although these policies may have a positive impact on human health, they open the door to excessive government control over food, which could restrict dietary choices, interfere with cultural, ethnic, and religious traditions, and exacerbate socioeconomic inequalities. These slippery slope concerns cannot be dismissed as far-fetched, because the social and political pressures are place to induce additional food regulations. To protect human freedom and other values, policies that significantly restrict food choices, such as bans on types of food, should be adopted only when they are supported by substantial scientific evidence, and when policies that impose fewer restrictions on freedom, such as educational campaigns and product labeling, are likely to be ineffective. Keywords: ethics, freedom, policy, public health, slippery slope, trans fats Trans fatty acids (or trans fats) are unsaturated trans-isomer clude information about trans fat content (Food and Drug fatty acids, which may be monosaturated or polyunsatu- Administration 2006). The FDA estimates that trans fat la- rated. Small amounts of trans fats occur naturally in meat beling could save up to 500 lives per year in the United and dairy products, but the largest source of these lipids in States by reducing the incidence of cardiovascular disease the human diet comes from artificial sources, such as par- (Food and Drug Administration 2006). Consumer groups tially hydrogenated vegetable oils used in cooking and food and public health organizations have argued that product preparation (Institute of Medicine 2002). Trans fats became labeling is not a sufficient response to the problem posed popular with food manufacturers, bakeries, and restaurants by trans fats, and that there should be a ban on all arti- in the 1960s, because they can enhance the taste of some ficial trans fats in food (Ban Trans Fats 2009; Center for foods and help to preserve texture. Trans fats used in frying Science in the Public Interest 2008; American Medical Asso- also are more durable than other types of oils and have a ciation 2008). Several major cities and counties (New York neutral taste (Severson 2003). City, Boston, Philadelphia, King County, WA, and Nassau A growing body of evidence has linked consumption of Country, NY), the state of California, and Puerto Rico have trans fats to cardiovascular disease (Woodside et al. 2008). heeded this call and passed laws banning the use of artificial According to a meta-analysis of four prospective cohort trans fats in restaurant food. More bans are likely to follow studies, a 2% increase in energy uptake from trans fats (Steinhauer 2008; Center for Science in the Public Interest is associated with a 23% increased risk of cardiovascular 2008). disease. Trans fats are also associated with sudden death While many view trans fat bans as an important pol- from cardiac causes (Mozaffarian et al. 2006). Trans fats are icy tool for promoting public health, others are disturbed thought to promote cardiovascular disease by increasing by the government’s encroachment on freedom and auton- levels of low-density lipoprotein (LDL or “bad”) cholesterol omy. ABC News’s John Stossell writes, “This week, New in the blood and decreasing levels of high-density lipopro- York became the first big city to ban trans fats. Gee, I’m all tein (HDL or “good”) cholesterol (Institute of Medicine for good health, but shouldn’t it be a matter of individual 2002; Ascherio 2006). According to some experts, replacing choice?” David White (2007) expresses a similar sentiment: artificial trans fats with healthier oils, such as olive oil or “Like smoking, the choice to eat high-calorie foods might canola oil, could save 30,000 to 100,000 lives per year in the not always be prudent. But government prohibition of that United States (American Medical Association 2008). choice is a remarkable confiscation of freedom.” National In January 2006, the Food and Drug Administra- newspaper columnist Walter Williams raises slippery slope tion (FDA) required that nutrition labels on foods in- concerns: This article is not subject to U.S. Copyright. Acknowledgments: This research was supported by the intramural program of the National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences (NIEHS), National Institutes of Health (NIH). The views expressed in this article are solely the views of the author. They do not represent the opinions of the NIEHS, NIH, or the U.S. government. I am grateful to Chris Portier and Bill Schrader for helpful comments. Address correspondence to David Resnik, National Institutes of Health, National Institutes of Environmental Health Sciences, Mail Drop NH 06 Box 12233, Research Triangle Park, NC 27709, USA. E-mail: resnikd@niehs.nih.gov ajob 27
The American Journal of Bioethics The nation’s food zealots have . . . started out with a small that mandatory labeling of products with trans fats reduces target—a ban on restaurant use of trans fats. Here’s what I consumption of trans fats, but there have been no studies on predict is their true agenda: If banning a fat that’s only two the effects of trans fat bans (Niederdeppe and Frosch 2009). percent of our daily caloric intake is wonderful, why not ban Trans fat bans could, paradoxically, reduce some unhealthy saturated fats, the intake of which is much higher? Then there’s behaviors but encourage others. Many food manufactur- the size of restaurant servings. Instead of a law simply requir- ers began using artificial trans fats in commercial products ing restaurants to label the calories in a meal, there will be laws setting a legal limit on portions. (Williams 2007) during the 1980s and 1990s to reduce the saturated fat and cholesterol content of food, because the medical consensus Should we embrace trans fat bans as a sound public at that time was that saturated fats and cholesterol are un- policy or should we be wary of this strategy for controlling healthy. As it turned out, trans fats are much worse for the the human diet? Are trans fat bans the best thing since sliced human heart than saturated fats; some saturated fats, such bread or the road to food fascism? In this essay I examine as those contained in peanut and canola oils, are good for the ethical arguments for and against trans fat bans (i.e., you; and moderate amounts of cholesterol in the diet are es- bans on trans fats in foods prepared by restaurants or other sential to health (Severson 2003). While I am not suggesting commercial food producers). I argue that while trans fat that there is no scientific basis for reducing the consumption bans may help to improve public health, they represent of artificial trans fats, I do think that much more research is a worrisome policy trend, because they open the door to needed on the public health effects of trans fat policies, so further restrictions on food. Though few people will mourn that we can avoid repeating the nutrition policy mistakes of the loss of artificial trans fats from restaurant food, the issue the past. here is much larger than that. At stake is a freedom that most of us exercise every day but often take for granted: the Economic Cost-Savings freedom to choose what we eat. The second argument for trans fat bans is an economic one. According to this line of thought, bans on artificial trans fats ARGUMENTS FOR TRANS FAT BANS can save potentially billions of dollars in health care and related costs by reducing prevalence and severity of cardio- Public Health Promotion vascular disease (Ban Trans Fats 2009). In the United States, The two main arguments for trans fat bans are consequen- over 80 million people (36% of the population) have car- tialist in form. According to the first argument, trans fat bans diovascular disease (American Heat Association 2009). The are justified in order to promote an important social good, direct and indirect costs of cardiovascular disease amount public health. Trans fat bans can promote public health by to an estimated $305 billion in the United States in 2009 reducing the consumption of trans fats, which could reduce (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention 2009a). If a the incidence and severity of cardiovascular disease. Ac- nationwide ban on artificial trans fats reduced the costs of cording to one estimate, totally eliminating artificial trans cardiovascular disease by only 10%, this would save $30 fats from the food supply in the United States would save billion per year. 50,000 lives per year (Center for Science and the Pubic In- The strength of the economic argument depends on the terest 2008). Trans fat bans are cut from the same cloth as empirical premise that trans fats ban will reduce the costs other laws that safeguard the food supply, such as such associated with cardiovascular disease. This assertion, like as quality and safety standards for restaurants and food the empirical premise in the public health argument, is also manufacturers, regulation of food additives, and product highly plausible, given what we know about the effects ar- labeling requirements (Fortin 2009). Food safety and qual- tificial trans fats on human health, but it is not unassailable. ity laws help to prevent food manufacturers from harming Consider the costs of smoking. For many years, health pol- the public with unsafe or unhealthy products, and they can icy analysts have assumed that smoking places enormous assist consumers in making healthy choices. Recent events, economic burdens on society by increasing costs related such as adulteration of powdered milk in China with the in- to lung cancer, pulmonary disease, cardiovascular disease, dustrial chemical melamine, which killed five children and and other health problems (World Bank 1999). Smoking sickened over 300,000, and contamination of peanut butter costs the United States nearly $200 billion per year in health with Salmonella in the United States, which killed nine peo- care expenditures and lost productivity (Centers for Disease ple and sickened over 570, illustrate the importance of food Control and Prevention 2009b). A recent study examining safety and quality as a public health matter (Barboza 2008; the lifetime costs of smoking found that smokers actually Martin 2009). cost society less than nonsmokers, because smokers die ear- The strength of the public health argument depends on lier. The investigators examined the costs of three cohorts: the empirical premise that trans fat bans will promote public an obese cohort, a smoking cohort, and a healthy living co- health. While this assertion is highly plausible, given what hort. The healthy living cohort cost society the most money, we know about the adverse effects of trans fats on the cardio- because they lived an average of 7 years longer than the vascular system, it is not indubitable. Because trans fat bans smoking cohort and 4.5 years longer than the obese cohort. have been in effect for only a few years, very little is known During those extra years of life, people in the healthy liv- about how they impact public health. One study has shown ing cohort had costs associated with various diseases of 28 ajob March, Volume 10, Number 3, 2010
Trans Fat Bans and Human Freedom aging, such as bone fractures, arthritis, stroke, dementia, on artificial trans fats do not have a major impact on food urinary-tract infections, and loss of hearing and vision (van consumers, since most people do not care whether they eat Baal et al. 2008). Some authors have disputed the policy products that contain these substances. People do not have implications of this study because it does not take into ac- a special fondness for artificial trans fats, but rather for the count costs of quality-adjusted life years lost (McPherson foods that contain them. Removing artificial trans fats from 2008). The debate over the costs of smoking suggests that cookies, crackers, hamburgers, and French fries will make we should be careful about making claims about the po- little difference to consumers as long as this does not affect tential cost-savings of trans fat bans. While there clearly is a how these foods taste, smell, look, or feel. Bans on artificial factual basis for claiming that trans fat bans can save society trans fats mostly affect food producers, not consumers. a great deal of money, more research is needed on the effects Second, even if some consumers have a strong prefer- of these policies, including effects on the food industry. ence for artificial trans fats, laws that ban commerce and trade in these substances can be justified to promote public ARGUMENTS AGAINST TRANS FAT BANS health. As noted earlier, trans fat bans fit into the safety and quality regulatory framework that operates in the United Restrictions of Freedom States and other industrialized nations. Banning trans fats The main ethical argument1 against trans fat bans is that is no different, in principle, from banning food additives these laws, whether at the local, state, or federal level, con- that have been found to be unhealthy, such as cyclamate stitute an unjustifiable restriction on the freedom to de- (Henkle 1999). The reasoning that justifies food safety and cide what one eats. One could argue that the ability to quality laws is similar to the reasoning that justifies other decide what one eats, though not important as freedom public health measures that restrict human freedom, such as of speech or religion, is an important freedom nonetheless. mandatory vaccinations, disease surveillance, and isolation First, food has a significant impact on one’s quality of life. and quarantine. Though freedom is an important value, it People take great pleasure in eating, preparing, and serv- can be overridden in some circumstances to promote impor- ing food. Food is more than mere nutrition: it is one of tant social goals, such as preventing people from harming life’s simple pleasures. Second, food has considerable eth- themselves or others, and promoting the health of the pop- nic, cultural, and religious significance. Different ethnic and ulation as a whole (Kass 2001; Childress et al. 2002; Gostin cultural groups have their own cuisines and culinary prac- 2007; Buchanan 2008; Gostin and Gostin 2009). tices. In any medium-sized city in the United States, one can find restaurants that serve Chinese, Japanese, Italian, French, Mexican, Indian, and Thai food. There are also many The Slippery Slope different foods associated with particular geographic re- A critic of trans fat bans could acknowledge that not many gions in the United States, such as Southern fried chicken, people have a particular fondness for artificial trans fats Texas barbeque, Boston baked beans, Philadelphia steak and that food safety and quality laws can be justified to sandwiches, and so on. Food also has religious significance, promote public health, but could maintain that there is a as different faiths have various rules, customs, and teach- larger issue at stake here: the continued erosion of dietary ings related to food (Montanari 2006). Third, food plays an freedom. Trans fat bans are very different from food safety important role in family traditions and customs. Food takes and quality laws because they aim to prevent consumers center stage at family reunions and at gatherings associated from making unhealthy choices, instead of preventing pro- with particular holidays, such as Thanksgiving, Christmas, ducers from causing harm. Requiring food manufacturers and Independence Day. Families also have special recipes to ensure that their products are not contaminated with handed down from generation to generation. Thus, the free- microorganisms that can cause severe illness or death is dom to decide what one eats is an important freedom that very different from preventing manufacturers from selling should not be restricted unnecessarily. products that increase the risk of cardiovascular disease if A proponent of trans fat bans can acknowledge that the consumed for many years, because most people will not vol- ability to decide what one eats is an important freedom but untarily choose to eat food that is contaminated or spoiled, still maintain that trans fat bans are justifiable. First, bans while people often choose to eat foods that can cause harm if eaten for many years. Bans on the use of trans fats in restau- 1. Mello (2009) has examined some of the legal issues concerning rant food would lead to additional bans on trans fats, which the trans fat policies adopted by New York City and other cities would open the door to further restrictions on the human and states, including preemption by federal laws and insufficient diet, since there is no difference, in principle, between ban- opportunities for public comment. According to Mello, one of the ning artificial trans fats and banning other unhealthy foods, problems with local policymaking on trans fats is that this could such as processed meats and sugared drinks. Today, trans create a patchwork of rules that will create compliance problems for fats; tomorrow, hot dogs. businesses and spark legal battles over preemption issues. Though Mello raises some important legal issues, her analysis does not Support for this empirical slippery slope argument get to the heart of the matter, since she does not voice any ethical comes from the following facts: (1) we already know about objections to trans fat laws. Rather, her article supports the view the adverse health effects of many foods and science is likely that trans fat policies should be made at the federal level, not the to discover more; (2) health advocates are likely to continue local or state level. to push for additional regulations; and (3) health-conscious March, Volume 10, Number 3, 2010 ajob 29
The American Journal of Bioethics consumers and politicians are likely to be receptive to the distinction between foods and food additives is not as additional regulations. For example, consumption of red clear as one might think. Many substances added to im- meat and processed meat increases the risk of colon cancer prove the taste, texture, flavor, color, or freshness of food, (Johnson and Lund 2007), and consumption of sugared such as sugar, corn syrup, yeast, citric acid, and vitamins, drinks, especially those high in fructose, increases the risk of might also be viewed as foods. It is not at all obvious how obesity, diabetes, and heart disease (Brown et al. 2008). Em- one could make a conceptually stable distinction between boldened by victories against trans fats, health advocates artificial trans fats and other lipids added to foods. A policy could go after red meats, processed meats, sugared drinks, framework that focused on specific kinds of fats defined as and other unhealthy foods (Chan 2008). “food additives” could collapse under social and political The social consequences of sliding down the slope to- pressure for additional food regulation. Second, although ward additional food regulation could outweigh any pub- there are powerful forces that would resist attempts to ex- lic health gains that might result. Since restrictions on the tend the scope of food regulation beyond trans fats, it is human diet can impact quality of life, family traditions, not clear to me that these forces would be able to hold the and cultural, ethnic, and religious practices, wide-ranging line. Restaurants and food connoisseurs who opposed trans attempts to control food choices could have adverse conse- fats bans in New York City, California, and other jurisdic- quence on society. Few people would want to live in a world tions could not resist effective campaigns by public health in which government health experts dictate what is on the organizations and consumer groups. menu or how it should be prepared. Additionally, increased regulation of the human diet could lead to social and economic injustices. Policies that TOWARD RATIONAL FOOD POLICIES make it more difficult to obtain affordable nutrition, such The empirical slippery slope argument developed in the as taxes on food, can exacerbate socioeconomic inequali- previous section cannot be easily dismissed as a flight of ties (Caraher and Cowburn 2005). For example, hot dogs, fancy, since it is firmly rooted in existing political, social, bologna, and other processed meat products provide an economic, and biological realities. To avoid the undesir- inexpensive form of protein, but they also are high in satu- able outcomes that could occur from excessive government rated animal fat, the consumption of which contributes to control over the human diet, food policy decisions should cardiovascular disease (Woodside et al. 2008). If the gov- be made with an eye toward not only promoting public ernment taxes or bans these foods on the grounds that they health but also preserving human freedom. One of the cen- contribute to heart disease, then low-income people might tral dilemmas in public health policy is how to balance need to seek other, more expensive sources of protein. health promotion and other important values, such as free- A standard response to an empirical slippery slope argu- dom and justice (Kass 2001; Childress et al. 2002; Gostin ment is to assert that the slide toward undesirable outcomes 2007). can be avoided by implementing rules, procedures, or def- To develop food policies that appropriately balance pub- initions designed to stabilize policy and practice (Lewis lic health and freedom, and therefore address slippery slope 1999). A proponent of trans fat bans could claim that so- concerns, it will be useful is to establish a set of conditions ciety can avoid excessive food regulation by distinguishing that must be met to restrict human freedom. These condi- between bans on food additives and bans on foods. A food tions can help to ensure that policy decisions will not be additive is a substance added to food to improve taste, tex- made willy-nilly, but will be appropriately articulated, re- ture, flavor, color, or freshness. Bans on cyclamates, which viewed, and justified (Kass 2001). The following are some are food additives that enhance sweetness, have not led conditions that can be applied to proposed policies that re- to bans on foods that enhance sweetness, such as sugar strict human freedom to promote public health (Childress (Henkle 1999). By limiting the scope of trans fat bans to et al. 2002): prohibitions on food additives, such as artificial trans fats, society can promote public health while safeguarding other r Effectiveness: there must be substantial scientific evidence values. that the policy is likely to be effective at achieving an A proponent of trans fats bans could also point out that important pubic health goal. there are social and economic forces in place that would r Necessity: there must be substantial scientific evidence counteract a move from trans fat bans to bans on other foods. that the policy is necessary to achieve the public health For example, tobacco companies, automobile manufactur- goal. ers, and many other corporations have mounted influential r Proportionality: the potential public health gains of the (and often successful) campaigns against government regu- policy must outweigh the adverse social impacts and lation. The food industry would be a powerful opponent of other moral considerations. any attempt to extend the scope of food regulation beyond r Least infringement: the policy must impose the least re- trans fats. strictions on freedom necessary to promote the public While I appreciate the merits of these critiques of the health goals. empirical slippery slope argument, I am not convinced that r Publicity: the policy must be justified to the public, with they defuse concerns about excessive food regulation. First, the reasons for restricting freedom clearly explained. 30 ajob March, Volume 10, Number 3, 2010
Trans Fat Bans and Human Freedom How might these conditions apply to trans fat bans? The food producers to follow specific rules, and impose penal- trans fat bans enacted by state and local governments may ties for noncompliance. Bans on particular food items are meet three of these conditions. Trans fat bans probably may the most restrictive methods of promoting public health, be effective, because, as mentioned previously, trans fat bans because bans prevent people from making some types of may help to promote public health, though more research dietary choices and they prevent food producers from sell- is needed. Trans fat bans may also meet the proportional- ing particular types of foods. ity condition as well, because the public health gains could Thus, although trans fat bans probably will help to pro- outweigh adverse social impacts and other moral consid- mote public health, a convincing argument can be made erations. Because few people have special preference for that governments have enacted these policies without de- artificial trans fats, trans fats bans probably do not have a termining whether other policies, which do not significantly significant impact quality of life, cultural, ethnic, or religious restrict human freedom, are effective at promoting public traditions, or family values. Trans fat bans will not exacer- health. A better way of dealing with the trans fat problem bate socioeconomic inequalities by increasing the price of would be give education and product labeling a chance to food, though more research is needed to verify this point. work, before resorting to the extreme measure of banning Trans fat bans also meet the publicity condition, because trans fats. By enacting food policies that limit the freedom they have been discussed and debated government hear- to choose what one eats only as an option of last resort, the ings, public comment meetings, and other public forums government can strike a fair balance between promoting (Mello 2009). public health and protecting human freedom (Wikler 1978; The trans fat bans that have been enacted thus far may Mytton 2007). not meet the other two conditions, however. The bans may not meet the necessity condition, because a combination of CONCLUSION other policies, such as education and mandatory labeling, While it is clear that consumption of artificial trans fats may be equally effective at achieving public health goals. poses a significant risk to human health, it is not clear how Proponents of trans fat bans have asserted that they are societies should respond to this risk. Numerous state and necessary, because the other methods for promoting public local governments in the United States have banned the use health are not effective enough, since consumers may not of artificial trans fats in restaurant foods, and other bans understand the risks of trans fats or heed warnings or advice may follow. Although these policies may have a positive (Ban Trans Fats 2009). However, this claim rings hollow, be- impact on human health, they open the door to excessive cause bans have been imposed before public education and government control over food, which could restrict dietary food labeling have been given a chance to work. Trans fats choices, interfere with cultural, ethnic, and religious have only been on the public’s radar screen since about traditions, and exacerbate socioeconomic inequalities. 2001. Prior to this time, people were more concerned about These slippery slope concerns cannot be dismissed as saturated fats in the diet (Severson 2003). FDA labeling and far-fetched, because the social and political pressures are voluntary labeling by fast food restaurants began in 2006, in place to induce additional food regulations. To protect but the movement to ban trans fats began before then. Ad- human freedom and other values, policies that significantly mittedly, educational campaigns and product labeling may restrict food choices, such as bans on types of food, should prove to be ineffective, but then again, they may not. The be adopted only when they are supported by substantial important point is that we simply do not have enough ev- scientific evidence and when policies that impose fewer idence at this time to declare that educational campaigns restrictions on freedom, such educational campaigns and and product labeling will fail and that some other policies product labeling, are likely to be ineffective. are necessary. If it turns out that other methods of decreasing the con- sumption of trans fats are as effective as bans, then trans REFERENCES fats bans also do not meet the least infringement condition American Heart Association. 2009. Heart disease and stroke as well. To develop this point, it will be useful to classify statistics, 2009. Available at: http://www.americanheart.org/ different trans fat policies with respect to how much they downloadable/heart/1240250946756LS-1982%20Heart%20and%20 restrict human freedom. Education involves virtually no re- Stroke%20Update.042009.pdf (accessed May 31, 2009). striction on freedom, because the objectives of education are American Medical Association. 2008. AMA supports ban of artifi- to convey information and enhance decision-making, not to cial trans fats in restaurants and bakeries nationwide. Press Release, manipulate or control individual choices. Mandatory food November 10. Available at: http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/ labeling is more restrictive than education, because label- pub/category/20273.html (accessed June 2, 2009). ing controls the decisions made by food producers, even though this helps to promote effective decision making by Ascherio A. 2006. Trans fatty acids and blood lipids. Atherosclerosis consumers. Taxation is more restrictive than labeling be- Suppl. 7(2): 25–27. cause it can place financial constraints on decisions made Ban Trans Fats. 2009. Available at: http://www.bantransfats.com by food producers and consumers. Food safety and qual- (accessed June 2, 2009).Barboza, D. 2008. China begins trial for 9 in ity standards are highly restrictive, because they require tainted milk scandal. New York Times, December 30, p. A8. March, Volume 10, Number 3, 2010 ajob 31
The American Journal of Bioethics Bren, L. 2004. Got milk? Make sure it’s pasteurized. FDA Consumer Johnson, I., and E. Lund. 2007. Review article: Nutrition, obesity and Magazine September–October. Available at: http://www.fda.gov/ colorectal cancer. Alimentary Pharmacological Therapy 26(2): 161–181. fdac/features/2004/504 milk.html (accessed June 2, 2009). Kass, N. 2001. An ethics framework for public health. American Brown, C., A. Dulloo, and J. Montani. 2008. Sugary drinks in the Journal of Public Health 91: 1776–1782. pathogenesis of obesity and cardiovascular diseases. International Lewis, P. 2007. The empirical slippery slope from voluntary to non- Journal of Obesity (London) 32(Suppl. 6): S28–S34. voluntary euthanasia. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 35: 197–210. Buchanan, D. 2008. Autonomy, paternalism, and justice: Ethical McPherson, K. 2008. Does preventing obesity lead to reduced priorities in public health. American Journal of Public Health 98: 15– health-care costs? PLoS Medicine 5(2): e37. 21. Mello, M. 2009. New York City’s war on fat. New England Journal of Caraher, M., and G. Cowburn. 2005. Taxing food: Implications Medicine 360: 2015–2020. for public health nutrition. Public Health and Nutrition 8: 1242– Montanari, M. 2006. Food is culture. New York: Columbia University 1249. Press. Center for Science in the Public Interest. 2008. Trans fat: On the way Mozaffarian, D., M. Katan, A. Ascherio, M. Stampfer, and W. Willett. out! Available at: http://www.cspinet.org/transfat (accessed June 2006. Trans fatty acids and cardiovascular disease. New England 2, 2009). Journal of Medicine 354: 1601–1613. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. 2009a. Chronic disease Niederdeppe, J., and D. Frosch. 2009. News coverage and sales of prevention and health promotion. Available at: http://www.cdc. gov/NCCDPHP/publications/AAG/dhdsp text.htm#2 (accessed products with trans fat: Effects before and after changes in federal May 31, 2009). labeling policy. American Journal of Preventative Medicine 36: 395–401. Centers for Diseases Control and Prevention. 2009b. Eco- Martin A. 2009. Peanut plant says audits declared it in top shape. nomic facts about. U.S. tobacco use and tobacco produc- New York Times February 5, p. B10. tion. Available at http://www.cdc.gov/tobacco/data statistics/ Mytton, O., A. Gray, M. Rayner, and H. Rutter. 2007. Could targeted fact sheets/economics/econ facts/index.htm (accessed May 31, food taxes improve health? Journal of Epidemiology and Community 2009). Health 61: 689–694. Chan, S. 2008. A tax on many soft drinks sets of a spirited debate. Severson, K. 2003. The trans fat solution. Berkeley, CA: Ten Speed New York Times December 16, p. A36. Press. Childress, J., R. Faden, R. Gaare, L. Gostin, J. Kahn, R. Bonnie, Steinhauer, J. 2008. California bars restaurant use of trans fats. New N. Kass, A . Mastroianni, J. Moreno, and P. Nieburg. 2002. Public York Times July 26, p. A1. health ethics: Mapping the terrain. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics Stossell, J. 2006. Trans fat ban is ‘Nanny State’ intrusion. 30: 170–178. ABC News, December 6. Available at: http://abcnews.go.com/ Fast Food News. 2006. McDonald’s unveils nutrition labeling. 2020/story?id=2705411&page=1 (accessed June 2, 2009). February 8. Available at: http://www.foodfacts.info/blog/2006/ van Baal, P., J. Polder, G. de Wit, R. Hoogenveen, T. Feenstra, H. 02/mcdonalds-unveils-nutrition-labeling.html (accessed June 2, Boshuizen, P. Engelfriet, and W. Brouwer. 2008. Lifetime medical 2009). costs of obesity: prevention no cure for increasing health expendi- Food and Drug Administration. 2006. Questions and an- ture. PLoS Medicine 5(2): e29. swers about trans fat nutrition labeling. Available at: http:// White, D. 2006. Take two servings of paternalism. The Amer- www.cfsan.fda.gov/∼dms/qatrans2.html#s5q5 (accessed June 2, ican December 21. Available at: http://american.com/archive/ 2009). 2006/december/take-two-servings-of-paternalism (accessed June Fortin, N. 2009. Food regulation. New York: Wiley. 2, 2009). Gostin. L. 2007. General justifications for public health regulation. Wikler, D. 1978. Persuasion and coercion for health: Ethical issues Public Health 121: 829–834. in government efforts to change life-styles. Millbank Memorial Fund Gostin, L., and K. Gostin. 2009. A broader liberty: J. S. Quarterly/Health and Society 56(3): 303–338. Mill, paternalism and the public’s health. Public Health 123: Williams, W. 2007. Trans fat ban. Townhall.com, January 10. 214–221. Available at: http://townhall.com/columnists/WalterEWilliams/ Henkel, J. 1999. Sugar substitutes: Americans opt for sweetness and 2007/01/10/trans fat ban (accessed June 2, 2009). lite. FDA Consumer Magazine November-December. Available at: Woodside, J., M. McKinley, and I. Young. 2008. Saturated and trans http://www.fda.gov/FDAC/features/1999/699 sugar.html (ac- fatty acids and coronary heart disease. Current Atherosclerosis Re- cessed June 2, 2009). ports 10(6): 460–466. Institute of Medicine. 2002. Letter report for dietary reference in- World Bank. 1999. Curbing the epidemic: Governments and the eco- takes for trans fatty acids. Available at: http://www.iom.edu/ nomics of tobacco control. Development in Practice Series. Wash- Object.File/Master/13/083/TransFattyAcids.pdf (accessed June 2, ington, DC: World Bank. Available at: http://www1.worldbank. 2009). org/tobacco/reports.htm (accessed June 2, 2009). 32 ajob March, Volume 10, Number 3, 2010
Copyright of American Journal of Bioethics is the property of Routledge and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.
You can also read